There is nothing
I want more than to become enlightened about the whole highly complicated
system of antagonisms that constitute the 'modern world' (Nietzsche).
Along
with Marx, Friedrich Nietzsche can be read as a great theorist and critic of
modernity who carried out a "ruthless criticism of all that exists"
(Marx 1975c [1843]: 142). His powerful broadsides against religion, morality,
and philosophy deploy a mixture of Enlightenment-inspired criticism and
anti-Enlightenment vitalism to attack the life-negating aspects of modern
culture. In addition, Nietzsche criticizes many of the institutions and values
of modern societies as oppressing bodily energies and creativity, while
blocking the generation of stronger individuals and a more vigorous society and
culture. In his appraisals of the modern age, Nietzsche developed one of the
first sustained critiques of mass culture and society, the state, and
bureaucratic discipline and regimentation, producing perspectives that deeply
influenced later discourses of modernity. Since his writings display cogent
insights into the origins, dynamics, culture, and personality-formations of
modern societies, Nietzsche deserves to be read in the narrative of social
theory, although he has been generally neglected in discussions of classical
theory (Baier 1981-1982 and Antonio 1995).
Although
he polemicizes against democracy, liberalism, and various progressive social
movements, Nietzsche's attack is at least partially carried out in a modern
Enlightenment spirit, negating existing ideas in the name of a better future.
Despite his keen appreciation for past cultures like classical antiquity and
defense of some premodern values, Nietzsche is very future and
present-oriented, attacking tradition while calling for a new society
and culture. An impetus toward innovation, involving negation of the old and
creation of the new, is therefore at the very heart of Nietzsche's complex and
often enigmatic theoretical work, which, in the spirit of modernity, affirms
development and transcendence of the old as crucial values for contemporary
individuals and society.
Nietzsche
wanted to transcend modernity for a new mode of culture and society that would
create stronger and more fully-developed individuals. He believed that new
potentials for individual creativity and for a "higher" form of
culture, made possible by the eruption of the modern age, were being curtailed
and suppressed by the prevailing social and political organization, requiring
radical socio-cultural change. This too, however, was in some ways a very
modern posture. Thus, despite assaults on modernity, Nietzsche exemplified the
very modern spirit of critique, and throughout his career attacked the
perennial and contemporary idols of the mind which he saw as obstacles to free
thinking and living.
Whereas
most readings of Nietzsche center on his philosophy or cultural critique, I
focus on his importance for the problematic of modernity and highlight the
insights that he presents concerning the constitution of modern culture and
societies, as well as his critique of how modernity inhibits the creation of
freer, happier, and healthier human beings. I attempt to show that Nietzsche's
writings contain a fascinating mixture of modern, anti-modern, premodern, and
what might be called "postmodern" impulses and positions which help
account for the contradictions of his thought. My thesis is that Nietzsche's
critique of modernity is a key element of his work and construct a reading
which interprets his major ideas in relation to his novel account and critical
analysis of the modern world.
Nietzsche's Life and Writings
Friedrich
Nietzsche was born in the rural, central German town of Rocken in 1844, the
same year in which Marx wrote his Paris Manuscripts and began his
encounter with modern capitalism. The son of a Lutheran pastor who died when he
was four, Nietzsche would eventually associate modern ideas with liberation
from what he considered to be the mystifying theology and stultifying
prejudices of his provincial childhood world.[2]
Reared by his mother, grandmother, and aunts, and adored by his sister
Elizabeth, Nietzsche's writings contain some misogynist themes, although, as I
show later in this chapter, he was one of the first to theorize gender and
gender difference within modern society, and also positively deployed figures
of women, generating a vast literature and debates over the topic of Nietzsche
and women.[3]
As
a youth, Nietzsche wrote poetry and excelled academically; he was awarded a
scholarship to the elite school at Pforta where students received an
outstanding classical education in a military-like disciplinary environment,
cut off completely from the modern world. Nietzsche developed a strong concept
of discipline and respect for martial values throughout his life, seeking to
become a cultural warrior against his age, engaging in spiritual battle and the
fight for a new culture.
At
18, Nietzsche entered the University of Bonn, and, after a year of boisterous
fraternity activity, including a duel and frequent drunkenness, experiences
replicated by Marx and Weber, he transferred to the University of Leipzig with
his classics professor Theodore Ritschl. Young Nietzsche soon after
distinguished himself as a top-flight student and deeply immersed himself in
the study of classical antiquity, cultivating a love for ancient Greece and
Rome that would shape his later thinking. Nietzsche periodically paid respect
to his love for the Greeks, writing:
Oh,
those Greeks! They knew how to live. What is required for that is to stop
courageously, at the surface, the fold, the skin, to adore appearance. Those
Greeks were superficial -- out
of profundity. And is not this precisely what we are again coming back to,
we daredevils of the spirit who have climbed the highest and most dangerous
peak of present thought and looked around from up there -- we who have looked down
from there? (1974: 38 and 1954: 683).[4]
At
the age of 24, Ritschl recommended Nietzsche for a professorship at Basel, even
though he had not yet completed the required Ph.D. On the basis of this
recommendation and a few published papers, Nietzsche was offered the job and
quickly awarded the necessary doctorate, even though he had not written a
formal thesis. Nietzsche began his short but illustrious academic career just
as the Franco-Prussian war broke out, and he volunteered and served as a
hospital orderly. After brief service on the front in France, he was assigned
to take sick troops back to Germany, became ill himself, and was forced to
leave the military. Yet he returned to Basel an enthusiast for military
adventures and values, and for some years after the war he defended the German
Reich and culture in lectures and publications.
The
young professor soon began work on his first book, The Birth of Tragedy,
the outline of which he claimed was thought out in the midst of the battle of
Worth (Nietzsche 1969 [1908]: 270). The text was denigrated or ignored in the
academic mainstream, but was affirmed by others as a brilliant and novel
interpretation of Greek culture, including Richard Wagner, whose work Nietzsche
hoped would promote a rebirth of German culture, and with whom he formed a
deep, albeit conflicted, friendship. Indeed, Nietzsche became a frequent
visitor at Wagner's house in Tribschen and a propagandist for the maestro's
music drama which he hoped could provide a basis for a new German culture.
Nietzsche
wrote during a period of great German economic expansion and industrialization
which he responded to in his writings, intensifying his critical project to
include the economy, social institutions, and politics, as well as culture.
Meteoric development of the coal and steel industries, manufacturing, finance,
and administration were propelling Germany into a global economic and military
power. The railway and telegraph systems provided an infrastructure for a
national market, and a powerful bureaucracy and dutiful and respected civil service
forged the basis for a modern state apparatus. In a climate of exuberant
nationalism, following Prussia's decisive military victory over France in 1871,
Bismarck unified Germany politically under his leadership. The enhanced
prestige of the Junker officer corps strengthened the hand of the old
landholding aristocracy, and gave added force to their antimodernist opposition
to liberalism and democracy. Intensified nationalism accompanied the expansion
of national armies and the major imperialist powers began more intensely
competing for colonies and markets.
But
whereas the young Nietzsche started out an enthusiastic nationalist and
believer that Wagner could help produce a strong German culture that could
unify the German nation culturally much as Bismarck was unifying it
politically, he soon became skeptical of both German nationalism and Wagner.
Bergmann (1987) suggests that Nietzsche should be read as a member of the
generation of 1866 which experienced German unification as a great generational
experience that produced the excitement of new possibilities, but was also a
source of later disappointments. From this perspective, the early Nietzsche's
search for a new culture was inspired by the perceived need to provide a great
culture to unify the new German nation. But Nietzsche then became disillusioned
with German philistinism, the dull nationalism of the German Reich, and came
more to identify with various other European cultures and to present himself as
a "good European."
Nietzsche
followed his impressive literary debut with a series of Untimely Meditations
which attacked, in the spirit of the Enlightenment, key figures and features of
Germany and the modern age while proposing ideas for cultural renewal. The
target of the first Meditations was the German writer David Friedrich
Strauss. Nietzsche read Strauss' Life of Jesus at twenty and was deeply
impressed with his philological dissection of the account of Jesus' life in the
gospels (Hayman 1980: 63).[5]
After paying homage to Strauss' earlier work, Nietzsche sharply criticized his
more recent writings which he saw as exemplary of the philistinism that was
ruling German life since its victory over France and unification, and which
blocked the rebirth of genuine culture that he desired (Nietzsche 1990 [1873]:
23ff).
Throughout
his Meditations, Nietzsche claimed that modern culture was
"barbaric" (i.e. a formless amalgamation of fragmentary competing
styles, ideas, and works), and he assailed the excessive rationalism,
egotistical individualism, shallow optimism, homogenization, and fragmentation
that he saw as characteristic of modern culture. In On the Uses and
Disadvantages of History for Life, Nietzsche argued that with the
proliferation of historical studies modern man was becoming paralyzed and
overwhelmed with historical knowledge (1990 [1874]: 87ff.), writing: "We
moderns... possess nothing which is truly ours." For Nietzsche, the
contemporary person assimilated an overwhelming amount of factual knowledge
that was trivial and did not shape a rich and formative common culture:
"And so all of modern culture is essentially inward; on the cover the
binder has stamped some title like 'Handbook of Inner Culture for Outward
Barbarians'" (1990: 105).
Believing
that modern individuals suffered from a weakened personality, Nietzsche wanted
the study of history to be put in the service of creating great personalities,
to help make possible a rebirth of genuine culture. During the 1870s, Nietzsche
was becoming increasingly disappointed with the philistinism of the new German
Reich and progressively intensified through the 1880s his critique of German
bourgeois culture, Wagner, Bismarck, German militarism, and the Reich. He
distanced himself from his search for a new culture based on Wagner's music dramas
and published a series of aphoristic works which promoted a spirit of
enlightenment and social critique, beginning with Human, All Too Human
(1986 [1878]).
Nietzsche's
turn to aphorisms exhibit a propensity to find a new way of writing,
self-expression, and argumentation -- a project that is itself akin to
modernist aesthetic practices. His aphorisms apply the spirit of Enlightenment
and experimental science against traditional religion, morality, and
philosophy, as well as against the homogenizing and oppressive tendencies of
the present age. His aphoristic writings seek to replace all obscurity,
superstition, and illusions of the past with clear, rigorous, and emancipatory
ideas that will serve human life and produce a new culture. Nietzsche also effectively
deployed the short essay, parables, narrative, and other story-telling devices,
and is considered one of the great writers of all time, as well as a major
thinker.
Severe
headaches also helped force Nietzsche to develop a more aphoristic style, allowing
him to work in short periods of extreme intensity, producing a veritable
explosion of ideas on a diversity of topics. His recurrent medical problems
highlighted for him the importance of the body and good health, topics that
became central to his thought. Indeed, ill health and dissatisfaction with
academic life forced Nietzsche to resign his Basel professorship; and during
the decade between 1878 and 1888, he often lived a solitary and unsettled life,
engaging in intense work and producing a large number of highly original books.
Henceforth, he was a man without a country or home, wandering through southern
Europe in search of better health, or optimal writing conditions. He withdrew
from many of his previous friendships, turning inward for inspiration and
material. During this period, Nietzsche became increasingly disgusted with the
German Reich and culture, and impressed with French and Italian culture.
During
the 1880s, Nietzsche came to insights which he believed were of crucial
importance to world culture. Utilizing the metaphor of an explorer charting new
seas and lands (1974 [1882]: 180-181, 283-4, passim), his visionary philosophy
was brilliantly sketched in his major literary work Thus Spoke Zarathrustra
(1883-1885), which presented his ideas in dramatic form. A steady stream of
books illuminated and developed these concepts, including The Gay Science,
Beyond Good and Evil, The Genealogy of Morals, Ecce Homo, Twilight
of the Idols, and The Anti-Christ. The late Nietzsche poured out
book after book, completing five in 1888, the last year before his permanent
madness.
While
Nietzsche has traditionally been presented as the archetype of the solitary
thinker, far removed from the turmoil of his age, recent studies have indicated
that his thought was attuned to the socio-political events of his time, and can
be productively read in the context of the relation of his writings to his
socio-political and historical environment. Bergmann (1987), Warren (1988), and
Detweiler (1990) document Nietzsche's deep immersion in the political
controversies of the day and studies have also chronicled the contradictory
political effects of his writing.[6]
Bergmann (1987) has shown that throughout the 1870s and into the 1880s,
Nietzsche was profoundly interested in the cultural and political events of the
day, reading newspapers, journals, and political pamphlets of the era. On the
whole, he came to despise all modern political movements and most form of state
politics, rejecting modern politics en toto while developing a form of cultural
politics that seeks social transformation through production of a new culture
and values.
Biographical
studies thus reveal that his political attitudes were shaped by the events of
the era and that his reflections on politics, society, and culture are an
important element of his thought. Hence, Nietzsche inaugurates a form of
"cultural politics" that assaults existing political institutions and
forms in the name of a cultural renovation and transformation of values that
reject existing modern social and political institutions in their entirety. I
thus read Nietzsche as engaging modern society and politics but attempting to
move beyond modernity to a new era.
Modern Society and Cultural Renovation
"Fundamental
innovations:.... In place of 'sociology,' a theory of the forms of
domination. In place of 'society,' the cultural complex, as my chief
interest" (Nietzsche 1968a [1883-1888]: 255).
Although
he rarely uses the term, Nietzsche's concept of the "cultural
complex" is an implicit organizing principle of his thought that
conceptualizes entire civilizations as cultural systems. The concept embraces a
wide historical panorama of different historical conjunctures, ranging from
ancient Greece and Rome, to Christian civilization, to the Renaissance,
Enlightenment, and contemporary mass society. The category of cultural complex
tightly condenses key defining features of a culture or era, compressing in a
highly charged figure of thought characteristics that illuminate a phenomena and
make possible enlightening comparisons. By dealing with cultural complexes
Nietzsche could speak of cultures as patterned wholes as opposed to
"society" which he saw as an aggregation of individuals. The term is
typical of Nietzsche's use of synoptic, organizing categories which he deploys
to compare different cultures and societies and which in its generalizing and
heuristic status anticipates Weber's conception of ideal types.
Nietzsche
saw culture in general as domesticating the body, submitting individuals to discipline and mechanisms of
social control. For Nietzsche, culture is a product of the sublimation of
bodily drives and it can either shape and form strong and healthy individuals,
or cause them to be so severely repressed that guilt, sickness, and decadence
result. In particular, Nietzsche thought that modern values replicated what he
considered to be "slave values" that supplanted an earlier
"master morality" (1967 [1887]). In this scenario, "ascetic
priests" took revenge on the strong and "domesticated" the body,
creating slave morality which channels ressentiment inward against the
body and outward against enemies of the herd. On Nietzsche's account, weaker
individuals resented the prerogatives of the stronger and carried out a
transvaluation of values, overturning previous master morality in favor of
slave moralities which promise salvation in a future heaven in exchange for
submission and obedience to social forces and institutions. Transforming
powerlessness and resentment into discipline and social control, ascetic
priests forge individuals into compliant "herds" who conform to the
dominant morality.
The
ultimate result of this process of cultural domestification through bodily
repression was an unparalleled control over the body in modern societies which
subjected individuals to repressive morality that stultified their instincts,
reducing the human beast to docile herd animals. Nietzsche ultimately traced
this long process of social rationalization and control to Socratic culture
that represented for him the triumph of reason over instincts, mind over body,
intellect over passion and drives. While Nietzsche saw pre-Socratic Greek
culture as producing healthy, vigorous, and strong bodies and personalities, he
believed that with the beginning of Socratic culture and "theoretical
man," Western culture largely oppressed the body and created weak
personalities.
Nietzsche
thus saw the origins of modernity in the Socratic cultural complex that worked
itself through Christianity, the Enlightenment, and modern mass societies and
cultures. Hence, whereas Marx made the development of the capitalist economy
the motor of modernity in the transition from feudal to modern society,
Nietzsche saw the origins of modernity much earlier in the constellation of
Socratic culture and privileged cultural forms over economics in his historical
narratives. Nietzsche's concept of "Socratic culture" thus denotes a
cultural complex which provides a key to his conceptualizing of modern culture
in contrast to premodern Greek culture, distinctions that function parallel to
the contrast between traditional and modern societies advanced by modern social
theory. These concepts provide Nietzsche with a historical optic and theory of
phases through which he analyzes the differences between modern and premodern
society, carries out a critique of modernity, and contrasts the life-enhancing
or life-negating potential of various historical phases and cultural complexes.
Socratic Culture and Theoretical Man: The
Origins of the Modern
"I seek to
understand out of what idiosyncrasy that Socratic equation
reason=virtue=happiness derives: that bizarrest of equations and one which has
in particular all the instincts of the older Hellenes against it"
(Nietzsche 1968b: 31).
Obviously,
Nietzsche discerns the origin of modern culture much earlier than Marx and
classical theory, interpreting the split between Greek tragic culture and
Socratic culture as the key to the emergence of the modern world that he sees
as the contemporary expression of Socratic culture. Unlike the other classical
social theorists, who posit a decisive rupture with the past and emergence of a
new modern society as a relatively recent event, Nietzsche sees the origins of
modernity in Greek culture in the split between tragic and Socratic culture --
much as Adorno and Horkheimer (1972 [1947]) saw the origins of Western
rationalism in Homer's Odyssey.
Nietzsche
constantly contrasted the vigor and unity of pre-Socratic Greek culture with
the lifelessness, fragmentation, and conformity of modern life (1967; 1968b;
1979; 1990). Yet he did not champion the harmony and grandeur of classical
Greece in an aesthetic vein ā la Winckelmann and classical German philology,
but instead found a more vibrant and powerful culture in pre-Socratic Greece.
Nietzsche's classical studies yielded a notion that the agon, or
contest, stood at the heart of Greek life. In Homer's Contest, he argued
that there were two types of contest in Greek culture: a dark and barbaric Eris,
reaching back to an age of cruelty, contrasted to competition between artists
and individuals of all walks of life that produced the distinctive
contributions of Greek culture (Nietzsche 1911 [1872]: 51ff.). Greek culture
was thus fundamentally agonistic with its athletes, poets, musicians,
philosophers, politicians, and others struggling for supremacy in public
contests. Whereas "modern educators" fear nothing so much as
selfishness or ambition, the Greeks unleashed the power of the individual for
the benefit of all (ibid: 58f).
For
Nietzsche, then, the competition of conflicting values, ideas, and ways of life
produced cultural diversity and a more vital culture which he contrasts to the
homogeneity and lifelessness of modern culture. These Greek cultural wars thus
exhibited a healthy, life-affirming culture that expressed bodily and aesthetic
sensibilities and that allowed the strongest and most creative to flourish.
Modern culture by contrast was homogenizing, repressive of the body, and
hostile to strong individuality. From his early work on The Birth of Tragedy
(1967 [1872]) to one of his last published texts Twilight of the Idols
(1968b [1889]), Nietzsche contrasted the vibrant Dionysian culture evident in
pre-Socratic Greece and early Greek tragedy with the more rationalistic
Apollinian strains evident in Socratic reason and later Greek tragedy.
Dionysian culture was eminently life-affirming, expressive of bodily energies
and passions, and bound together individuals in shared cultural experiences of
ecstasy, intoxication, and festivals, which Nietzsche believed created strong
and healthy individuals and a vigorous culture.
In
Nietzsche's view, Socratic culture was a response to the breakdown and
fragmentation of tragic Greek culture which it attempted to replace with a set
of shared, homogeneous values, theoretical norms, and procedures, based on
Socratic logic and reasoning, which would replace the warring gods of the
Greeks with a more unified rational culture. In a sense, Socratic culture thus
provided a cure for a cultural emergency with extreme rationalism coming to
curb the strong, warring impulses that had been released and that
Socrates/Plato believed were out of control.[7]
The result was an equation of reason and knowledge and virtue, making reason
the instrument of both truth and morality (1968b: 33).
Thus,
the Socratic cultural complex replaced what Nietzsche saw as the profound
pre-Socratic tragic vision of suffering and redemption through culture with the
Socratic optimism that reason can discover truth and produce a good life (1967
[1872] and 1968b [1889]). For Nietzsche, the triumph of Socratic theoretic man
provided the origins of modern rationalism and Enlightenment optimism and was
counterpoised to a tragic pessimism, which in the spirit of his early mentors
Schopenhauer and Wagner perceived great philosophy and art as the teachers and
redeemers of humanity and the instruments of strong, healthy cultures.[8]
Nietzsche saw Socratic culture as a force that was formative of the modern
period, but with life-negating results (for example, 1968b [1889]: 29ff.).
"Socrates" for Nietzsche was thus a symbol of decay, of atrophying
life-instincts in which reason came to dominate the body and the passions, a
process that intensified over the centuries.
For
Nietzsche, the celebration of Socratic "theoretical man" also
submitted culture to a subjectification, in which reason and rationalization
come to form a cultural complex hostile to the body, strong individuality, and
cultural diversity. Western culture is thus a form of subjectified culture for
Nietzsche whereby reason and rationalization negate the body, individuality,
and submit people to life-negating and homogenizing social control and
discipline. The Socratic cultural complex also generated a split between inner
and outer experience, and thus between subjective and objective culture, which
produced a fetishism of inwardness, valuing subjective spirit and reason over
external nature. Excessive evaluation of subjectivity produced both a
repression of the body and a crisis of representation, as there was a split
between subjective experience and external social reality. Nietzsche believed
that Western culture greatly overvalued ideas and reason, negating nature, the
body, and the objective realm of experience, thus producing a highly
subjectified cultural complex in which culture was seen as an expression of
subjectivity and valued because it cultivated personalities -- as opposed to
strong bodies, social institutions, or nature.
On
Nietzsche's view, the Socratic cultural complex generated a repressive
rationalism that became the central principle of modern culture, dominating
philosophy, the economy, the state, and everyday life. For Socratic culture,
the passions, body, and feelings are subordinate to reason, which emerged as
the ruling principle of philosophy and life. Nietzsche's life-work would be
dedicated to delineating the multifarious ways in which this principle
permeated modern societies, becoming a constitutive principle -- a theme that
would later be taken up by Weber, Lukācs, the Frankfurt school, and then
Foucault and much postmodern theory.
Nietzsche,
however, should not be read as an irrationalist who rejects modern reason and
all forms of rational thought and inquiry tout court. His first proposed
solution to the cultural and political malaise of the modern era was to
revitalize the Greek cultural complex that harmonized Apollinian and Dionysian
components, in order to create a new culture in the contemporary era. The
"Apollinian" represented the principle of form, order, and
individuation traditionally associated with Greek culture, while the
"Dionysian" represented those powers of intoxication, disorder, and
the dissolution of the individual ego in collective ecstasy and sensual surrender.
Intense Dionysian passion should therefore be harmonized, spiritualized, and
refined by Apollinian form. Classical Greek drama, especially Sophocles,
represented for Nietzsche a profound combination of the Apollinian and
Dionysian, linking aesthetic forms with tragic vision, profound harmony with
great suffering and passion, and the delineation of individual fate against the
backdrop of human finitude and powerlessness. Rather than rejecting the
Apollinian principle, Nietzsche thus calls for a synthesis and conjures the
ideal of an "artistic Socrates" who would combine the powers of
reason and creativity, the rational with the irrational.
Nietzsche
at first saw such a project exemplified in Richard Wagner's music theater but
became critical of its philistinism, sentimentalism, and lack of strong ideas.
In his middle writings, Nietzsche turned to an appreciation of a mode of
critical Enlightenment thought, though he criticized its pretensions and
limitations and always opposed a dissected Enlightenment rationalism cut off
from the body, passions, and instincts. Yet Nietzsche believed that a certain
sort of sublimation would create strong and healthy bodies and personalities
and like the other critical social theorists can be read as calling for a
reconstruction of Enlightenment reason rather than simply as an irrationalist.
Instead of merely condemning sublimation or inwardness, Nietzsche criticized
repressions of natural drives which turned them against themselves, exerting
cruelty and guilt through the mechanisms of conscience. Nietzsche opposed to
this form of self-repression a sublimation that refines natural instincts in a
creative and pleasurable manner.
Moreover,
the "artistic metaphysics" which the young Nietzsche champions can be
read as a celebration of aesthetic modernity, as a continuation of the romantic
project of the renewal of culture and life through art.[9] The return to Greece can therefore be
seen as an attempt to deal with modern problems and to provide contemporary
solutions which will produce a new future. On this reading, Nietzsche wishes to
combine premodern values with the modern project of perpetual self-overcoming
and transcendence to a higher stage of life,and thus a new
"postmodern" future. Indeed, a pathos of "the future" runs
through the entirety of Nietzsche's works. His early writings deal with the
future of educational institutions, the music of the future, and a future
rebirth of the higher culture of the Greeks.[10]
From
Christianity to Mass Society
add: good quote
on Christianity
In
Nietzsche's view, Christianity continued the main features of the Socratic
cultural complex, profoundly contributing to the subjectification of culture
and repression of expressive life energies. The universalism of Catholicism
contributed to homogenizing of the Western mentality and its rationalized
theology contributed to intellectual and societal rationalization.
Protestantism in turn exaggerated inwardness and individualism, in which
individual reason became the organon and the judge of truth.
On
the whole, however, Nietzsche saw Christianity as anachronistic and irrational.
In an aphorism on "Christianity and antiquity," Nietzsche is
incredulous that individuals still believe in "a justice which accepts an
innocent man as a substitute sacrifice; someone who bids his disciples drink
his blood" (1986 [1878]: 65-66). In Nietzsche's view, Christianity
represses bodily instincts, promotes an unhealthy sense of sin and guilt, and
generates unparalleled denial of the body and the senses. Although Nietzsche is
sometimes accused of being an irrationalist he assaulted the Christian cultural
complex precisely because of its irrationality and attack on the body and this
world. Jesus Christ, he claimed, "promoted the stupidifying of man, placed
himself on the side of the poor in spirit and retarded the production of the
supreme intellect" (Nietzsche 1986 [1878]: 112). Nietzsche also dissected
attacked the Christian transvaluation of values which declared strength and
wisdom as bad, while lowliness, humility, and submission were deemed
"good"; this promotion of a slave morality excessively valuated
spirit over body and promoted general societal repression and regression (1967
[1887]).
Nietzsche's
critique of Christianity was accompanied by a critique of morality. He sought
to abolish the "higher ideals" by showing their human-all-too-human
origins in "lower" strivings, needs, and frailties (1986 [1878] and
1966 [1886]). His studies provide "genealogical" accounts of the
genesis of morality and other higher ideals and embody modern skepticism,
suspicion, Enlightenment critique, and experimental thought and writing. In his
critique of morality, religion, and philosophy, Nietzsche denies the reality of
ideal or transcendental existences of any sort and strongly affirms a secular,
this-worldly orientation.
Nietzsche
described his aphorisms as "percepts of health" for free spirits
(Nietzsche 1986: 210), and they can be read as compendiums of modern secular
critical thought that would enable his reader to engage in enlightened
thinking. Nietzsche was especially critical of morality which he believed
oppressed individuals by imposing universalistic and repressive strictures on
individual behavior. The universalist ethos of morality suppresses the
particularity of individual drives, needs, and passions and is thus inherently
repressive. Morality also cultivates excessive subjectivism and inwardness,
creating unhealthy concerns with guilt, shame, and conscience. Highly
idealistic, morality represses and devalues bodily energies and passions and is
thus fundamentally life-denying in its dominant forms.
Undermining
its foundation will, Nietzsche believes, "undermine our faith in
morality" (1982 [1881]: 2). Morality works, he claims, through a
"certain art of enchantment," thus his diagnosis will work toward
demystification and disenchantment. From this perspective, Nietzsche's
offensive against morality carries through in the domain of values precisely
the process of disenchantment that Weber saw as the very dynamic of modernity.
In the modern cultural complex, Socratic values were rationalized and carried
forward in the Enlightenment and democratic revolutions, and institutionalized
in contemporary modern societies. For Nietzsche, only the Renaissance provided an
exception to this process of increasing social rationalization and the
weakening of strong individuals through social morality and religion. The
result was weak individuals, dominated by the "ascetic priests" of
morality and religion, who formed an indistinctive mass of docile herd
conformists.
Nietzsche
presented the modern incarnation of the Socratic "theoretic man" in
his conception of "the Last Man" who makes his own reason the measure
of the real (1954 [1883-8]: 129f) and who is devoid of creativity, originality,
and passion. This for Nietzsche was the mark of decadence and herd conformity,
a total surrender to the values and mode of life of the contemporary era. For
the Last Man (i.e. the most recent contemporary man) is totally content with
its lot and blinkingly accepts contemporary morality and values: "No
shepherd and one herd! Everybody wants the same, everybody is the same; whoever
feels different goes voluntarily into a madhouse" (1954: 130). This figure
anticipates Weber's conception of the Iron Cage and Marcuse's notion of
"one-dimensional man" (1964) who accepts its slavery and conformity
without question or revolt.
Nietzsche's
attack on "theoretic man" and slave morality can thus be read as a
critique of modernity, which has produced a condition of leveling and
homogeneity that Nietzsche saw as decadence and nihilism. Yet in addition to
criticizing modern values, Nietzsche was also concerned to construct a code of
values for the present age. Nietzsche consistently assailed guilt and
"remorse of conscience" (1968b [1889]: 23f) and affirmed the values
of "being natural," as well as strength, egoism, will, and the
"manly virtues." He increasingly championed the values of the body,
life and health, affirming ascending life as the source of values and declaring
that whatever intensifies and enhances life is good, while what diminishes and
inhibits life is deemed bad.
Nietzsche
consistently critiqued the Western conception of the "rational
subject" which portrays reason or mind as a "higher" faculty governing
the body. With Marx, he affirmed a materialist perspective that took seriously
human needs and drives, although his theory of human nature was more vitalist
and naturalist than Marx's synthesis of Feuerbach and the German humanist
Bildung tradition which emphasized the full development of the individual.
Nietzsche also attributed Christianity a stronger role in repressing
individuals than Marx, though his critique of religion powerfully promoted the
secular trends characteristic of modern thought, situating Nietzsche as a
champion of this-worldly and secular thought ā la Marx and the Enlightenment.
His polemics against Christianity exude the vitriolic sarcasm for which he
would become infamous and take to a higher level the Young Hegelian critiques
that deeply influenced the early Marx.
Nietzsche
often championed critical rationality, science, and knowledge as positive
forces of social transformation, and thus can be read as part of a
reconstructed critical Enlightenment tradition. Rejecting the "highest
ideals" of Western culture, he opposed an experimental philosophy and
"little truths" to empty generalizations of Enlightenment
rationalism: "It is the mark of a higher culture to value the little
unpretentious truths which have been discovered by means of rigorous method
more highly than the errors handed down by metaphysical and artistic ages and
men, which blind us and make us happy" (Nietzsche 1986 [1878]: 13). He
valued experimental science and critical thought as the highest ideal and
polemicized against the pretensions of idealist philosophy and religion (see
Nietzsche 1982 [1881]: 101, 185, 204 and Nietzsche 1974 [1887]: 110, 253, 324
passim).
In
the spirit of Enlightenment, Nietzsche also polemicizes against metaphysics,
arguing that it illicitly generalizes from ideas in one historical epoch,
projecting them upon the entirety of history. Against this form of
philosophical universalism, Nietzsche argues "there are no eternal
facts, just as there are no absolute truths. Consequently, what is needed
from now on is historical philosophizing, and with it the virtue of
modesty" (Nietzsche, 1878, 1986: 13). Nietzsche thus criticized the
idealism, absolutism, and universalism of traditional philosophy and values
from a critical Enlightenment historicist perspective. In a powerful philosophical
critique anticipating later critiques of metaphysics, he assailed the concept
of enduring knowledge, the notion of a metaphysical world, presenting
metaphysical thought -- in a modernizing vein -- as a thoroughly obsolete mode
of thinking. He attributes the "metaphysical need," at the heart of
Schopenhauer's philosophy, to primitive yearnings for religious consolation for
the sufferings of life and urges "free spirits" to liberate themselves
and pursue thinking and living experimentally (Nietzsche 1986 [1878]:
8).
Against
metaphysics, Nietzsche, like Marx, champions historical and physical
explanations, rejecting all obscurantist thinking and writing. His assault on
metaphysics can, therefore, be read as a critique of traditional thought that
clears the way for a thoroughly modern mode of thought.[11]
This theme is encapsulated in his notion of a "free spirit," which he
describes as an individual "who thinks differently from what, on the basis
of his origin, environment, his class and profession, or on the basis of the
dominant views of the age, would have been expected of him. He is the
exception, the fettered spirits are the rule," who take up their
"position, not for reasons, but out of habit" (Nietzsche 1986: 108).
Nietzsche's
critique thus contributed to development of a form of modern thought that was
this-worldly, historical, and focused on the present. Nietzsche's conception of
the "death of God" described the contemporary era that no longer
believed in transcendent values and in which a materialistic skepticism
reigned. But Nietzsche did not see this feature of modernity as emancipatory
per se and equated it with nihilism and decadence, a failure to create original
values and as expressive of a depletion or exhaustion of creative
life-energies. Against nihilism, Nietzsche called for the creation of values
that would be life-affirming and original, positioning superior individuals
against society. Yet he did not champion an unrestrained release of desire and
individual passion, calling instead for self-discipline and authority as key
elements of forming superior individuals. Nietzsche believed that strong
cultures such as ancient Greece, Rome, and the Renaissance practiced
self-discipline and provided authority that enabled individuals to be stronger
and more alive. Modern cultures, by contrast, lacked strong belief and
individuality, promoting mediocre herdlike thought and behavior:
We modern men,
very delicate, very vulnerable and paying and receiving consideration in a
hundred ways, imagine in fact that this sensitive humanity which we represent,
this achieved unanimity in forbearance, in readiness to help, in mutual
trust, is a positive advance, that with this we have gone far beyond the men of
the Renaissance. What is certain is that we would not dare to place ourselves
in Renaissance circumstances, or even imagine ourselves in them: our nerves
could not endure that reality, not to speak of our muscles. This incapacity,
however, demonstrates, not an advance, but only a different, a more belated
constitution, a weaker, more delicate, more vulnerable one, out of which is
necessarily engendered a morality which is full of consideration. If we
think away our delicacy and belatedness, our physiological ageing, then our
morality of 'humanization' too loses its value at once -- no morality has any
value in itself -: we would even despise it" (1968b [1889]: 89-90).
Liberalism,
Democracy, and Nationalism: Nietzsche's Critique
Nietzsche
thought that modern democracy, liberalism, and enlightened social movements
contributed to the regression of "modern man" behind the more vital
and powerful individuals of the Renaissance. Nietzsche consistently championed
ancient Greece and the Italian Renaissance as paradigms of strong, vigorous
cultures. His strategy was to choose past ideals which could serve as models or
norms for future "greatness." Greek and Renaissance cultures affirmed
the body, were secular, developed science and technology, were highly aesthetic,
and produced strong individuals-- all Nietzsche's ideals. These ideals, he
believed were concentrated in strong individuals like Julius Caesar, Caesar
Borgia, and the "great men" of the Renaissance. Nietzsche's normative
contrasts are supported by a distinction between sickness and health, between
descending and ascending life. His texts exult in an affirmation of life
energies and criticize everything that suppresses and inhibits the full
expression of primary instincts. His assault on religion, morality, and the
herd-conformity of modern societies is thus unleashed from the standpoint of an
ideal of the free and uninhibited flow of life energies, an unrestrained
expression of instinctual powers.
Likewise,
he argues that the democratic, liberal, feminist, anarchist, and socialist
movements are expressive of declining life, of sickness, of resentment. All are
manifestations of Socratic culture that posit reason over passion, ideas over
life, and all are also manifestations of modern leveling and homogenizing
tendencies, and are thus anti-life, helping to produce weak individuals and
cultures. In opposition to liberal cultural tolerance, Nietzsche advocated
cultural war which he believed would generate cultural diversity and a
stronger, more creative culture and individuals. Although Nietzsche's assault
on liberalism and other progressive social movements contain elitist and
anti-democratic attitudes, one also finds some positive positions on democracy
in his writings, as when Nietzsche presents the democratization of Europe as
irresistible and a "link in the chain of those tremendous prophylactic
measures which are the conception of modern times and through which we
separate ourselves from the Middle Age" (1983 [1880]: 376).
Nietzsche
presents political and socio-economic modernity here as providing the
foundation upon which future ages can build a better society and protect
themselves against barbarism and tyranny, writing: "Democratic
institutions are quarantine arrangements to combat that ancient pestilence,
lust for tyranny: as such they are very useful and very boring" (Nietzsche
1983: 383). This passage indicates Nietzsche's dual attitude toward democracy
quite clearly: on one hand, it is useful as a counterforce to tyranny, but it
is boring and promotes mediocrity. Later, Nietzsche will sift out all positive
elements toward democracy and be purely negative.
Although
some of Nietzsche's ideas on race were taken up by German fascism, their
concept of a German master-race and anti-semitism were far from Nietzsche's own
thought. Nietzsche was a strong critic of German nationalism and, as Kaufman
has demonstrated (1950), he was also critical of anti-semitism and various
proto-fascist values with which he has sometimes been associated by both his
champions and his critics. Although Nietzsche took up some Darwinian
categories, he inverted Social Darwinism by arguing that often the slaves, the
weaker, used cunning and intelligence to subjugate the stronger (1967; also
1968b: 75-6). He also argued that the Darwinian concept that self-preservation
was the fundamental human drive was misleading, writing: "The wish to
preserve oneself is the symptom of a condition of distress, of a limitation of
the really fundamental instinct of life which aims at the expansion of power
and, wishing for that, frequently risks and even sacrifices
self-preservation" (1974: 291-292).
Nietzsche
thought that the will to power and struggle were more fundamental than a will
to survive, to mere self-preservation, and that cultural diversity and struggle
would produce a genuinely healthier and stronger culture. Thus, rather than
racial separation or purity, Nietzsche believed that mingling of different
races and the development of a multicultural society in which different groups
competed would create a stronger European polity that would overcome the banal
nationalisms and national chauvinisms of his day. Moreover, Nietzsche
constantly theorized gender, class, national, and ethnic differences and thus
emerges as a theorist of difference against the homogenizing trends of
modernity and the tendencies of theorists to wipe out these differences in a
more generalized concept of human beings.
To
be sure, Nietzsche said many problematical things about women, workers, and
various cultures and nationalities, but he also had some sharp insights into
the differences between classes, genders, and nations, and believed that
affirmation of difference and particularities created stronger individuals and
societies. Moreover, as I argue in a later section, his concept of
multiperspectival seeing requires that one try to overcome the biases of one's
social position and perceive things from many perspectives, thus Nietzsche
anticipates postmodern theories of perspectivism and their celebration of
difference and otherness -- a theme I return to later in this chapter.
Nietzsche
consistently presented himself as a "good European" and advocated
"repudiation of national, class and individual vanity" (1983:
363). Thus, despite comments about "blond beasts" which would seem to
connect him with German fascism, Nietzsche celebrated cultural diversity and
Europe, anticipating contemporary multicultural theory, and attacked narrow
nationalism, anti-semitism, and the belief that any one nation constituted a
"master race." Yet he was generally hostile toward socialism,
anarchism, feminism, and other political movements of the day. In general,
Nietzsche equated Christianity and democratic political movements as
expressions of resentment of the weak against the strong and as devaluations of
this world, this existence, in favor of another world, an ideal future. Both,
in his view, exude pity and sympathy for the disadvantaged and advocate
equality and the well-being of all.
Crucially,
Nietzsche advocated a cultural politics that opposed the politics of his day,
especially the welfare-state politics of Bismarck. Thus, his attacks on
democracy, liberalism, and socialism are directed at the form of the first
welfare state developed in his day in Germany. He saw all of these movements as
manifestations of Socratic culture that helped produced societal
rationalization and that destroyed individuality. Anticipating the critiques of
Max Weber, Nietzsche believed that socialists would increase the tendencies
toward massification and cultural mediocrity because their ultimate goal is
"to manage more cheaply, more safely, more equitably, more
uniformly." On attaining power, they would attempt to perfect the modern
state's already growing regimentation. Speaking of "iron chains" and
"fearful discipline," Nietzsche warned that socialism threatened to
institute a "fundamental remolding, indeed weakening and abolition of the individual"
(1882 [1881]: 109, 131-132, 187). Associating socialism with premodern despotic
regimes, he believed that it would recreate "Chinese conditions" in
Europe and that its modern means of administration would produce even
"more complete subservience" and would show the harmful effects of
"all accumulations of state power" (Nietzsche 1986 [1878-1880]:
173-174; 1974 [1882]: 99, 338; and 1968a [1883-1888]: 463-464.
Putting
Nietzsche's ideas in context, one could argue that he was criticizing precisely
the weak and specious democracy evident in Wilhelmine Germany and that he was
thus one of the first critics of the perversion of democracy in modern
societies and of the leveling and homogeneity emerging in the new mass
societies. He thus produced one of the first critiques of the modern welfare
state. Likewise, his criticism of socialism can be read as a dissection of
German Social Democracy and its similarities to the sort of welfare state
bureaucracy being promoted by Bismarck. Indeed, Germany under Bismarck and the
Kaiser exhibited features of a bureaucratic and authoritarian welfare state and
"democracy" was merely formal and an ideology legitimating
authoritarian rule -- a position that Nietzsche shared with Marx. One could
also argue that the socialism that Nietzsche was attacking was precisely the
vulgar forms of "crude communism" and German socialism Marx attacked
in the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, that he and Engels
disparaged in The Holy Family and The German Ideology, and that
Engels castigated in Anti-Duhring (cite sources).[12]
Moreover,
Nietzsche's positive comments on Napoleon can be read as an expression of his
hatred of German nationalism and hopes for a united Europe, a dream of which
Napoleon was an early avatar. Indeed, both Caesar and Napoleon, two of
Nietzsche's cultural heros, were much more internationalist than nationalist.
Indeed, Nietzsche's critique of nationalism emerges as one of his major
contributions to contemporary thought. Whereas Marx saw nationalism as
epiphenomenal to the capitalist economy and believed it would disappear with
internationalist socialist revolution, Nietzsche saw the force and virulence of
nationalism, its irrational attraction, and what was new and original about it;
i.e. how it was connected with the new idol of the state. Nietzsche
continuously attacked both nationalism and the institutions like the state and
mass culture which promoted it.
Thus
one could read Nietzsche's attack on liberal democratic theory as providing a
specific condemnation of the German authoritarian welfare state in the Germany
of the Kaiser and Bismarck, with its anti-socialist laws, its cultural
mediocrity, nationalism, and its oppressive politics.[13]
Indeed, Nietzsche systematically and intensely assailed German culture and
nationalism from his Untimely Meditations, writing in the mid-1870s,
until the end of his literary activity in the late 1880s (see Nietzsche 1990
and 1968b). He equated nationalism with cultural homogenization, banality,
philistinism, and demagogic manipulation, reserving some of his most vitriolic
sarcasm for German nationalism, as when he blames German newspapers, beer, and
nationalism for German stupidity and mediocrity.
It
was precisely Nietzsche's attack on cultural homogenization, nationalism, and
philistinism that has endeared him to avant garde subcultures and artistic
movements, rebellious individuals, and opponents of the existing society.
Herbert Marcuse spoke of "the liberating air of Nietzsche's thought,
cutting into law and order" (1964: 216), and praised Nietzsche's
celebration of eros, play, and art, as well as "total affirmation of the
life instincts" (1955: 121). Indeed, Nietzsche's continued attraction to
cultural and philosophical radicals, evident in the current Nietzsche
appropriation in poststructuralist and postmodern theory, is found in his
attacks on cultural homogenization and defense of cultural diversity and Dialectic
of Enlightenment. Likewise, his sharp appraisals of the capitalist economy
and modern state have won sympathy for Nietzsche in many quarters.
Critique
of the Modern Economy and State
"...our
modern noisy, time-consuming industriousness, proud of itself, stupidly proud,
educates and prepares people more than anything else does, precisely for
'unbelief" (Nietzsche 1966: 69).
Nietzsche was highly critical of the
social institutions and values of modern societies which he saw as life-denying
and oppressive of strong individuality. Although he was presented by Lukācs
(1980) as an apologist for an imperialistic capitalism, in fact he loathed what
he saw as its base concern for merely monetary and bourgeois values, its alienated
labor, and its tendency to turn everyone into "industrious ants"
(1982a [1881]: 126-7). Like Marx, Nietzsche assailed the modern tendency to
reduce all value to mere utility, although he failed to grasp the specific
economic dynamics behind this process that Marx analyzed through the profit
imperative and commodity form. Attacking the hegemony of utilitarian values and
self-interest in a society of mediocrity, Nietzsche wrote;
Common natures
consider all noble, magnanimous feelings inexpedient and therefore first of all
incredible. They blink when they hear of such things and seem to feel like
saying: "surely, there must be some advantage involved; one cannot see
through everything." They are suspicious of the noble person, as if he
surreptitiously sought his advantage. When they are irresistibly persuaded of
the absence of selfish intentions and gains, they see the noble person as a
kind of fool; they despise him in his joy and laugh at his shining eyes....
What distinguishes the common type is that it never loses sight of its
advantage, and that this thought of purpose and advantage is even stronger than
the strongest instincts; not to allow these instincts to lead one astray to
perform inexpedient acts -- that is their wisdom and pride (1974: 77).
This
attack on utility and self-interest is parallel to Marx's attack on the
reduction of all values to those governed by exchange value which calculated
value in terms of self-interest and a narrow sense of material gain. Whereas
Marx championed altruism and Nietzsche egotism, he opposed the narrow concepts
of egotism and self-interest which merely interpreted these things in economic
terms. Nietzsche also carried out an all-out assault on capitalist values of
mendaciousness, flattery, sycophancy, and what he sees as a leveling into
mediocrity (1954 [1883]: 163-166). Distinguishing between "actors" in
the marketplace and "inventors of values" in a section on "The
Flies in the Marketplace" in Thus Spoke Zarathrustra, Nietzsche
uses the metaphors of pesky flies to denote the purveyors of the goods,
services, and values of the modern economy, and to exhort his readers to flee
from its temptations and seductions (ibid).
A
strong critique of the machine and the machine age is also present in
Nietzsche: "The machine of itself teaches the mutual cooperation of hordes
of men in operations where each man has to do only one thing: it provides the
model for the party apparatus and the conduct of warfare. On the other hand, it
does not teach individual autocracy: it makes of many one machine and of
every individual an instrument to one end. Its most generalized effect
is to teach the utility of centralization" (Nietzsche 1983 [1880], 366).
In this passage, it is as if Nietzsche had read Marx's analyses in the Grundrisse
and Capital concerning the dialectic of technology in capitalist
modernity. As Marx analyzes it, capital multiplies the productive powers of
labor through introducing new modes of cooperation and centralization, while
the consequent specialization robs individual labor of its creativity and
autonomy and binds the worker to the machine -- although Marx ultimately sees
more productive potential in the powers of cooperation whereas Nietzsche saw
only flattening out and homogenization, pointing to their quite different
concepts of the social.
Nietzsche
describes the energies set forth by the machine as "lower,
non-intellectual" (1983: 366), concluding: "It makes men active
and uniform -- but in the long run this engenders a counter-effect, a
despairing boredom of soul, which teaches them to long for idleness in all its
varieties" (1983: 367). He claimed that wage workers under capitalism are
worse off than slaves, because they are at the "mercy of brute need"
and employers who ruthlessly exploit them, concluding that:
the workers of
Europe ought henceforth to declare themselves as a class a human
impossibility and not, as usually happens, only a somewhat harsh and
inappropriate social arrangement; they ought to inaugurate within the European
beehive an age of a great swarming-out such as never been seen before, and
through this act of free emigration in the grand manner to protest against the
machine, against capital, and against the choice now threatening them of being compelled
to become either the slave of the state or of the party of disruption (1982a
[1881]: 125-127.
In
this passage, Nietzsche clearly advocates individualist revolt against the
capitalist machine, though he rejects joining the opposition party ("of
disruption") because he believed that all social movements are rooted in
the herd psychology of resentment of higher types. He also developed a
vitriolic attack on the modern state, finding it to be a "new idol"
that is "the coldest of all cold monsters," run by annihilators"
who continuously lie and relie. "Everything about it is false,"
Nietzsche claims, and it "devours... chews... and rechews" its
citizens (1954 [1883]: 160-163). Nietzsche consistently attacked as well German
nationalism, writing: "If one spends oneself on power, grand politics,
economic affairs, world commerce, parliamentary institutions, military
interests -- if one expends oneself in this direction the quantum of
reason, seriousness, will self-overcoming that one is, then, there ill be a
shortage in the other direction" (1968b [1889]: 62). Nietzsche is
distinguishing here between culture and the state and is clearly championing
the former over the latter, writing: "All great cultural epochs are epochs
of political decline: that which is great in the cultural sense has been
unpolitical, even anti-political" (1968b: 63).
Nietzsche
thus provides one of the first radical appraisals of the modern state as an
instrument of repression, homogenization, and mediocrity and can thus be read
as a sharp critic of modern politics. Nietzsche was "anti-political"
in the sense that he believed contemporary mass politics led to herd
conformity, leveling of individuality, and mass manipulation and
homogenization. Indeed, his condemnation of the state is bound up with his
critique of mass society and culture which he sees as homogenizing, massifying,
and harmful to vital life energies, creativity, and superior individuality.
Nietzsche's contributions to social theory thus revolve around his powerful
critical assessments of the modern state, mass society and culture, and their
normalizing and homogenizing tendencies.[14]
For
Nietzsche, the state and the marketplace were bitter antagonists against
culture and he saw both the modern state and society as leveling individuals,
producing mediocrity and cultural backwardness, as well as generating mass
hysteria such as nationalism and anti-Semitism. The modern state and society
level status and value hierarchies, reducing ideals and tastes to the lowest
common denominator and producing mediocre individuals. Consequently, Nietzsche
took on the key institutions of modernity in his critical optic. Yet unlike
Marx and Engels, he did not think that a new modern economy, society, and state
could be formed that could realize the promises of modernity. Thus, Nietzsche
combines highly modern ideas and impulses with distinctly antimodern positions.
Nietzsche
also sees the importance of new modes of communication and technologies in the
development of modernity: "The press, the machine, the railway, the
telegraph are premises whose thousand-year conclusion no one has yet dared to
draw" (Nietzsche 1880, 1983, 378). Yet on the whole, Nietzsche was
pessimistic about the impact of modern social processes. For the most part, he
felt that modern society and culture had become so chaotic, fragmented,
"arbitrary," and devoid of "creative force" that it has
lost the resources to create a higher culture and ultimately advanced the
decline of the human species. He especially thought that the press and mass
culture were forces of degeneration and mediocrity, focusing attention on the
trivial, superfluous, and sensational, and creating homogenization and
conformity.
Reversing
the optimism of classical theorists concerning the positive benefits of
association and growing voluntary integration of individuals into the
institutions and practices of modern societies, Nietzsche believed that
"society" as a form of culturally reproduced solidarity was
dissolving (1974 [1882]: 302-304l see also 1969b [1887]: 121-126l 1968a
[1983-1888]: 150; and 1968b [1889]: 93-93) and he saw social conformity and
domination as a threat to individuality. Indeed, he had an almost visceral
repulsion against mass society, arguing: "every association makes us
shudder slightly" and that "all contact... 'in society' -- involves
inevitable uncleanliness" (Nietzsche 1974 [1882]: 342 and 1966 [1886]:
226). Thus, while classical social theorists saw modern society as helping
develop individuality, Nietzsche saw a sharp antithesis between the individual and
society and saw modern society as oppressive to the development of
individuality.
In Nietzsche's view, two complementary
trends were evident that were eroding the promises of social modernity. On one
hand, modern society was fragmenting into warring groups, factions, and
individuals, without any overriding purpose or shared goals. On the other hand,
it was leveling individuals into a herd, bereft of individuality, spontaneity,
and creativity. Both trends were harmful to the development of superior individuality
and thus Nietzsche was sharply critical of each. Yet his social critique
generated powerful insights into social conformity and massification.
Superior
Individuality, Difference, and Social Roles
"The problem
of the actor has troubled me for the longest time" (Nietzsche 1974: 316).
Nietzsche's
texts also contain acute psychological analysis based on scrupulous
self-observation, study of the classics of the moral life, and the close study
of human beings. The psychological turn in Nietzsche's thought represents a
move within modern thought to more closely dissect the human psyche and the
inner life. Applying methods of observation developed in the study of nature to
the study of morality and the inner life, Nietzsche's thought intensifies the
concern with psychology that would mark the development of a differentiated and
fractured modern psyche, which Freud and other later psychologists would study,
establishing psychology as a discipline. Nietzsche's aphoristic texts thus
provide an important step in the self-scrutiny of the individual that is a
constitutive aspect of modernity and that anticipate the development of modern
psychology.
Indeed,
Nietzsche considered himself the first great psychologist, who explored the
terra incognita of the labyrinth of the modern psyche, though his mode of
analysis is closer to what I would call philosophical or cultural critique then
to "psychology" in the sense of the academic discipline that
developed with Freud and his successors. Part of cultural modernity, as
Habermas would remind us (1981), is the differentiation of various academic
disciplines and of fields of human experience, like society or the psyche, as
domains of an increasingly specialized academic division of labor. Classical
theory, we shall see, emerged before the extreme specialization of disciplines
like sociology and psychology, and thus combined philosophical, cultural,
political, psychological, and sociological issues in the attempt to articulate
the many dimensions of modernity.
Although
Nietzsche carried out a critique of ascetic ideals, he also advocated
discipline, sublimation, severity, and strength which would produce superior
individuals. Individuality was thus the creation for him of those who were able
to overcome their weaknesses and to produce stronger and healthier
personalities. "Self-overcoming" required transcendence of all of
one's infirmities, but also of all that society has made of one. Nietzsche
believed that modern individuals were "decadent" because their
life-instincts were atrophying and because they docilely submitted to social
domination. On Nietzsche's analysis, ressentiment was a major feature of
modern individuals who resented the prerogatives and capacities of the strong.
Modern individuals who did not themselves advocate strong values or exhibit
strong personalities were, Nietzsche argued, carriers of a modern nihilism that
no longer believed in any great values or ideals (Nietzsche 1968a: 7ff).
"Nihilism"
for Nietzsche signified a contemporary condition of cultural exhaustion and
decadence which required a transvaluation of values and development of a new
culture (1968a: 3ff). Culture for Nietzsche fundamentally consisted of an
"ordering of rank" (Rankordnung) that established higher and
lower values and Nietzsche calls for a revaluation of values, an overturning (Unwertung)
of the highest values and establishment of new values that would promote
stronger individuals and a more creative culture. His Ubermensch,
therefore, is a superior individual who overcomes the decadent values and is
able to create new life-affirming values and a stronger and more life-affirming
culture.
Developing
superior individuality requires overcoming social determinism and herd
conformity, pitting the individual against society. Nietzsche believed that
some individuals could exert their will to power to create higher, more refined
selves and one key to Nietzsche's ideal is his overcoming of the mind/body
dualism and his interpretation of freedom as liberation from societal
determinism. In particular, Nietzsche's free individual must be free from
morality, religion, and society and free to fully develop one's own
potentialities. In the following passage, Nietzsche indicates how art allows
"freedom above things" and the demands of morality and other
repressive institutions:
we need all
exuberant, floating, dancing, mocking, childish, and blissful art lest we lose
our freedom above things that our ideal demands of us.... We should be able
also to stand above morality -- and not only to stand with
anxious stiffness of a man who is afraid of slipping and falling any moment,
but also to float above it and play. How then could we possibly
dispense with art -- and with the fool? (1974 [1882]: 164).
Authentic
art was privileged by Nietzsche precisely because it cultivated the senses,
imagination, and other aspects of the mind and body, allowing individuals to
enter a realm that transcended conventional morality and social norms.
Nietzsche championed art as the most powerful enemy of the ascetic ideal and
the ultimate source of cultural vitality. The crisis in modern culture is
partly rooted in the fact that aesthetic sensibilities have been savaged by the
repressive forces of rationality, social rationalization, and mass culture and
society, thus art has been relegated to the margins of society. For Nietzsche,
however, these rationalizing forces must be constrained by aesthetically rooted
values. Free spirits were needed who would experiment with art, ideas, and life
and who would create new values and a new culture that would produce in turn
higher human beings.
On the whole, Nietzsche located superior
individuality in the body and denied the existence of a free subject or will --
concepts that were mythical in his view. Overcoming mind/body dualism,
Nietzsche praised the body's superior "intelligence" and treated the
ego as its "instrument" (1969 [1883]: 61-6, 86, 118, 120). In
addition, Nietzsche saw the "subject" as a mere construct, an
idealized sublimation of bodily drives, experiences, and a multiplicity of
thoughts and impulses. This "little changeling," Nietzsche
complained, this subject, "is believed in more firmly than anything else
on earth," but is a mere illusion created out of modern desperation to
have a well-grounded identity. For Nietzsche, "the doer" is
"merely a fiction added to the deed -- the deed is everything" (1869b
[1887]: 45). For Nietzsche, "the subject" was thus merely a shorthand
expression for a multiplicity of drives, experiences, and ideas. Nietzsche
broke with unified notions of the subject, arguing: "My hypothesis:
subject as multiplicity" (1968a: 270). Nietzsche saw the rational subject
celebrated by philosophy as a bundle of drives and impulses, some of which are
not even conscious. Moreover, the subject was a product of modern culture and
society which produced docile, disciplined, and conformist herd individuals.
Indeed,
some of Nietzsche's deepest insights pertain to how modern individuals and
their morality and values are products of modern society. In a prescient
anticipation of role theory, Nietzsche saw that modern societies were producing
a differentiated set of occupational, professional, and gender roles, that
imposed conventional and conformist behavior on individuals. Further, Nietzsche
was one of the first major theorists to articulate class, race, and gender
differences in a sustained and serious manner, and while he made many
masculinist comments about women he had some important insights into gender
differences. In a passage in the Gay Science, for example, Nietzsche
notes how men create "the image of woman, and woman forms herself
according to this image," (1974: 126), suggesting the social construction
of femininity and the way men are able to get women to conform to their own images
of what women should be. He also discusses the ways that women are socialized
into chastity via religion, morality, and social roles -- and are then thrown into marriage
where they are supposed to put aside sexual abstinence to satisfy their
husbands. Further:
Young
women try hard to appear superficial and thoughtless. The most refined simulate
a kind of impertinence. Women
easily experience their husbands as a question mark concerning their honor, and
their children as an apology or atonement. They need children and wish for them
in a way that is altogether different from that in which a man may wish for
children. In sum, one cannot be too kind about women (1974: 128).
Nietzsche
also anticipates "difference feminism" in passages where he suggests
that women's biological condition, in particular their ability to bear
children, generate important differences between men and women: "Pregnancy
has made women kinder, more patient, more timid, more pleased to submit; and
just so does spiritual pregnancy produce the character of the contemplative
type, which is closely related to the feminine character" (1974: 129).
Nietzsche also wrote that women were superior in learning to use masks and
distancing themselves from social roles than men, exhibiting a "lightness
of being" and talent for dissimulation not found in many men (1974:
316-317).
Such
passages -- with deep insight into the social situation of women and sympathy
for them -- should be contrasted to Nietzsche's more misogynist discourse to
capture characteristic contradictions of his thought. Derrida (1979 [1976]) and
some French feminist thinkers, eager to recuperate Nietzsche for their
positions, argue that Nietzsche really advocates "feminine" values
and that he privileges the figure of woman in his work (see the discussion in
Many claim that Nietzsche has more affinities with feminism than other modern
theorists -- claims hotly contested by others (see Schutte 1986). On this
issue, like so many others, "Nietzsche" is a contested terrain and
his texts support widely variant interpretations.[15]
Thus,
Nietzsche was one of the first major theorists to theorize gender differences
between men and women as socially constituted in modern societies. The main
target of his critique was not women but rather the professionally specialized,
conformist, family-oriented, church-going male who he saw as the bearer of
mediocrity. Of course, his sociological insights were often undercut by
essentializing discourses that privileged men over women and espoused
masculinist values. Yet on a personal level, Nietzsche himself had many
constructive personal relations with intellectual women, often used the
feminine as a positive metaphor, and was in many ways more "feminine"
than "masculine" himself -- in terms of how these concepts were then
socially constructed.[16]
In
addition, Nietzsche stressed the limitations of more rational modes of
communication, so it would be wrong simply to dismiss his thought as
masculinist tout court. For Nietzsche, authentic communication and social bonds
are anchored in shared feelings and the body, and not in abstract linguistic
interchange.[17] Nietzsche
rejected the notion that words were mirrors of natural or conceptual objects,
depicting them as "fictions," which "mask" bodily drives
and introduce inevitable distortions into communication because they are
impersonal and collective while experience is personal and individual.
Nietzsche
thus valorized expressive, bodily, and aesthetic modes of communication, while
pointing to the limitations of rational and linguistic social interaction. Yet
he did not advocate an "anything goes" relativism and constantly
stressed the importance of strong modes of thought that did not flinch from
looking coldly and without illusions into the negative aspects of life. More
than ever, Nietzsche believed, the present times call for a cultural leadership
who can endure "seeing reality as it is," in all its
multiplicity, chaotic uncertainty, and harshness, whatever the costs (1968b
[1889]: 163). Nietzsche's superior individuals would thus live fully,
dangerously, with contradictions, yet without illusions, and would be able to
benefit from the full range of cultural diversity and difference.
While
classical social theorists like Durkheim saw social roles as providing
potentials for an expansion of individual thought and behavior, Nietzsche
believed that occupants of the new specialized occupations and social
functions, especially the professions, tended to over-identify with their roles
and engage in inauthentic "fabrication" or "simulation."
During the Middle Ages, individuals were stuck in fixed roles whereas modern
individuals "become convinced" that they "can do just about
everything and can manage almost any role" (1974: 302-3). But, he
felt, they act hesitantly, without strength, asking themselves: "How ought
I feel about this?" They are so engaged in simulating effectiveness and
identify so strongly with their roles that they "really become actors"
and have trouble being "anything else... The role has actually become
the character" (Nietzsche 1986 [1878-1880]: 39-40; see also 1982a [1881]:
157; 1974 [1882]: 302-304; 1966 [1886]: 26, 218; and 1968a [1883-1888]: 328).
Whereas
most modern social theorists claimed that social actors gained self-reflexivity
against traditional roles and had an expanded repertoire of possibilities from
which to choose, Nietzsche maintained that modern role-playing is governed by
sterile models that destroy particularity, spontaneity, and individual
self-expression. Modern role players act instead in a highly conventional and
unreflective manner, adapting "many roles" which they play
"badly and superficially" in the mode of a mechanically acted
"puppet-play." Wearing these social masks reduces individuals, he
believes to "shadows" and abstractions, turning individuals into
simulacra. Anticipating Baudrillard's postmodern theory (1993), Nietzsche
contended that simulation is so pervasive that it is hard to distinguish
between the role and the person, between the simulated behavior and the real
individual. Modern role players are so docile, Nietzsche believed, that they
"prefer the copies to the originals" (Nietzsche 1983 [1873-1876]:
84-86l see also 1986 [1878-1880]: 136; 1974 [1882]: 232-233; 1969a [1883]: 268,
300, 302; and 1968b [1889]: 26-7).
Thus,
whereas Marx and other classical social theorists stressed that society
produced new forms of fragmentation and solidarity, Nietzsche saw these
modern forces as producing primarily homogeneity and fragmentation, thus
articulating a primarily negative optic on social modernity. But in addition to
seeing the negative features of social modernity, classical social theorists
stressed that modern modes of sociality, association, and cooperation provided
positive resources to create strong individuals, to produce wider
communication, and more democracy. Thus, unlike the classical social theorists
who believed that modern societies provide the resources to address its
problems and to institute social change, Nietzsche believed that a new culture
was necessary to regenerate individuals and social life. Whereas classical
social theorists believed that their new sciences of society were able to
identify indispensable resources for social progress and to provide knowledge
of how to improve and reform society, Nietzsche declared that sociologists and
social reforms exemplified "the decaying forms of society"
(1968b [1889]: 91).
Nietzsche
often spoke of a conflict between these roles and the genuine person, but by
equating the authentic self with the body, he reversed the usual privileging of
"higher" spiritual, ideal, or transcendental features of the
personality. Moreover, Nietzsche believed that the herd conformists who
submitted to dominant roles and behavior lacked the personal resources to cope
with the socio-cultural disintegration and fragmentation that was a feature of
modern societies. For this reason, he believed that resentment was rampant,
easily redirected, and dangerous. Yet Nietzsche pointed to the ideal of a
completely different type of social actor who dons masks without totally
identifying with their roles or losing their sense of self in their social
functions. These "genuine" actors "dissimulate" in order to
perform and observe themselves in their social roles. They are able to
establish "distance" from their roles, engage in a multiplicity of
roles and functions, to bear solitude and aloneness, to avert manipulation, and
to be capable of benevolence and modesty. Their behavior thus exhibits an
independent and creative quality missing in the more conformist social actors
(Nietzsche 1986 [1878-1880]: 136; 1982 [1881]: 156; 1974 [1882]: 130-133, 321;
1966 [1886]: 160).
Sometimes
Nietzsche's superior individuals act out of the sheer delight of putting on
masks, thus escaping the "heaviness" of fixed identities, and at
other times they use them to cunningly avoid threats, overcome enemies, and
exercise command (e.g. Homer's Odysseus). But this sort of dissembling is
purposive without any confusion of self and role (Nietzsche 1982a [1881]: 156;
1974 [1882]: 131-132). They utilize their roles to "become who we are
-- human beings who are new, unique, incomparable, who give themselves laws,
who create themselves" (1974 [1882]: 266. Such reflexive and clever role
players can originate in any social stratum. For example, Nietzsche argued that
today's subjugated strata (e.g. "lower classes," "Jews,"
and "women") develop highly refined role-playing skills and unusual
adaptability (1974: 316-317). These individuals are not
"domesticated" or absorbed in their roles, but use them to retain and
amplify their "multiplicity" and bodily "intelligence."
Nietzsche
held that such "sovereign individuals" appear in all types of
societies. Although they are always relatively rare, they have exceptional
influence on patterns of cultural and social development. The ideal of the
reflective actor is thus closely linked to Nietzsche's idea of a potential
cultural leadership stratum, capable of ushering in a higher form of
civilization. The same process of social selection that
"domesticates" weak individuals, thus has reverse effects among
sovereign types. Since they instinctually transgress norms, they are subjected
to disciplinary actions in all societies. Hence, the same conditions that
produce "leveling" and mediocrity give rise to "exceptional
human beings" (Nietzsche 1968a [1883-1888]: 80, 460-464; 1966 [1886]:
138-139, 176-177; 1968b [1889]: 118, 232).
While
Nietzsche believed that the mixing of peoples and cultures in modern societies
has devastating effects on most people, overwhelming and confusing them with
difference, he believed that it makes sovereign types "stronger and richer
than ever before." Rather than being confused and paralyzed by diversity,
these superior types find the ubiquitous cultural clashes and highly divergent
values, ways of life, and groups to be sources of growth and power. They are so
flexible and adaptable that they are "increasingly independent of any determinate
milieu" (Nietzsche 1966 [1886]: 174-177). Because of their
"manifold" and "mixed features," they grasp "the
perspective character of existence" -- that each person's body, biography,
and location are unique optics and sources of a nearly infinite range of
possible points of view. Since they themselves draw power from difference, they
see the plurality of possible people, experiences, and values to be a resource
and they are able to respect and benefit from difference themselves (Nietzsche
1974 [1882]: 336-337).
Nietzsche
envisaged the "highest type" of person to have "the greatest multiplicity
of drives in the relatively greatest strength that they can be endured."
Being the "richest in contradictions," these people would have
"antennae for all types" of humanity (Nietzsche 1968a [1883-1888]:
150, 479, 507). This perspectival type of being was at the core of Nietzsche's
aspirations for "overcoming" modern mediocrity and Socratic culture.
He stressed emphatically the utter futility and undesirability of modern
efforts to harmonize contrary spheres of values and ideas. The capacity to orient
to the world from fundamentally different and conflictual perspectives subverts
the abstract rationalism, one-sidedness, and mediocrity characteristic of
modern selves and theory. Nietzsche's superior individuals would be able to
grasp the particular, uncertain, incomplete, disjunctive, and
"experimental" nature of knowledge. They would be uninhibited enough
to live without warrants in the midst of difference and to embrace, thrive on,
and, even, will difference (Nietzsche 1966 [1886]: 160, 110-111, 145-146).
Nietzsche
saw modern societies as producing both new forms of herd conformity and new
forms of cultural diversity that would make possible the development of
superior individuals. Nietzsche attacked those conditions that prevented higher
individuality and that produced massification and mediocrity. He directed his
cultural critique against the heartland of Northern European culture,
especially German culture and male professional culture that were the main
forces of conformity and leveling. Although Nietzsche sometimes made derogatory
remarks about what he considered to be inferior cultures and nations, he also
championed cultural diversity and difference. He saw Christianity, morality,
and social conformity leveling individuals into a homogeneous herd, and
fragmenting into incommensurate social groups. Both tendencies have indeed
accelerated since Nietzsche's day, so his analysis of the contradictory
features of social modernity and critique of its leveling tendencies continues
to be relevant. Against the oppressive features of social modernity Nietzsche
developed the ideal of superior individuals who would be distinguished in part
by a perspective way of seeing and knowing and the ability to appropriate a
multiplicity of perspectives. We shall present this ideal as a model for a new
type of modern theory in the following section and take on the limitations of
Nietzsche's social thought in a concluding section.
Perspectivism and the Critique of Modern
Theory
"There
is only a perspective seeing, only a perspective 'knowing'; and
the more affects we allow to speak about one thing, the more complete
will our 'concept' of this thing, our 'objectivity,' be" (Nietzsche 1969:
119).
Nietzsche's
attack on Christianity and otherworldly idealism can be read as a culmination
of Enlightenment modernity, as a modernizing demystification and secularization
of the world. For Nietzsche, as with the Young Hegelians, modernity comes into
its own with the death of God, though Nietzsche drew more consequent philosophical
implications, arguing that with this event, there exists no more solid, stable,
eternal foundation for values and ideas. In a radically transitory, finite, and
unstable world, there can be no foundation for philosophy or values. Nietzsche
overturned and revalued (Umwertung) the highest philosophical values,
championing becoming over being, appearance over reality, this world over the
"true world," and body over spirit (1968b: 35ff). He thus anticipated
Derrida's deconstruction, taking apart traditional philosophical hierarchies,
and the attack on foundationalism associated with postmodern theory.
In
addition, Nietzsche's perspectivism denied the possibility of affirming any
absolute or universal values: all ideas, values, positions, and so on are
posits of the existing individual, constructs of a will to power, which are to
be judged according to the extent to which they do or do not serve the values
of life and strong individuality. For Nietzsche there are no facts, only
interpretations, and he argued that interpretation was constituted by the
interpreter's perspectives and was thus inevitably laden with presuppositions,
values, biases, and limitations. For Nietzsche, a perspective was thus an
optic, a way of seeing, and the more perspectives one had at one's disposal,
the more one could see, the better one could understand and grasp specific
phenomena. To avoid one-sidedness and partial vision one should learn "how
to employ a variety of perspectives and interpretations in the service
of knowledge" (Nietzsche 1969: 119).
On
one hand, the notion of perspectival seeing indicates the limitations whereby
each individual's body, history, and location restricts what one can see. On
the other hand, the doctrine points to the necessity of learning to see from a
variety of positions and cultivating perspectival seeing as part of superior
individuality. Nietzsche believed that: "every elevation of man brings
with it the overcoming of narrower interpretations; that every strengthening
and increase of power opens up new perspectives and means believing in new
horizons" (1968a: 330). Acquiring perspectival seeing enables individuals
to overcome one-sidedness and thus to grasp aspects of phenomena previously
overlooked. It also enables individuals to overcome one-sided modes of thought.
We usually
endeavor to acquire a single deportment of feeling, a single
attitude of mind toward all the events and situations of life -- that above all
is what is called being philosophically minded. But for the enrichment of knowledge
it may be of more value not to reduce oneself to uniformity in this way, but to
listen instead to the gentle voice of each of life's different situations;
these will suggest the attitude of mind appropriate to them. Through thus
ceasing to treat one-self as a single rigid and unchanging individuum
one takes an intelligent interest in life and being of many others (Nietzsche
1983 [1880]: 195-196).
Nietzsche's
assumption is that reality is too complex and many-sided to be grasped from a
single perspective: "A multiplicity of hypotheses, for example, as
to the origin of the bad conscience, suffices still in our own time to lift
from the soul that shadow that so easily arises from a laborious pondering over
a single hypothesis which, being the only one visible, is a hundredfold
overrated" (Nietzsche 1983 [1880]: 304). A single hypothesis can provide
but a one-sided grasp of things and thus requires refinement and rethinking. In
the Genealogy of Morals (1983), where he explicated this doctrine,
Nietzsche provides an interpretation of ascetic ideals, insisting that ascetic
ideals are very different in artists, philosophers, priests, and scientists.
There is thus no essence of the ascetic ideal, or single hypothesis that
explains them, but a wealth of phenomena that require different interpretations
and valuations.[18]
The
concepts of perspectival seeing and interpretation provide Nietzsche with a
critical alternative to essentialism: objects do not have an inherent essence,
but will appear differently according to the perspective from which they are
viewed and interpreted and the context in which they appear. He spoke of his
own "search for knowledge being manifested in the dream of having the
"hands and eyes" of many others and of being "reborn in a
hundred beings" (1974 [1882]: 215). Cultivating this approach required learning
to see and interpret -- "habituating the eye to repose, to patience,
to letting things come to it; learning to defer judgement, to investigate and
comprehend the individual case in all its aspects" (Nietzsche 1968b
[1889]: 65).
This
passage points to another virtue of a perspectival optic: learning to grasp the
specificity and particularity of things. Nietzsche mistrusted the distorting
function of language and concepts which required perspectival seeing and
interpretation to grasp the particularity and specificity of concrete
individual phenomena. Perspectival seeing allowed access to "a complex
form of specificity" (Nietzsche 1968a [1883-1888]: 340) which made
possible a more concrete and complete grasp of the particularities of
phenomena. Seeing from conflicting perspectives also opened people to
appreciation of otherness and difference, and to grasp the uncertain,
provisional, hypothetical and "experimental" nature of all knowledge.
Thus,
the multiperspectival approach allows the theorist to grasp the particularity
and concreteness of individual phenomena. In this sense, it is similar to
Marx's concept of mediations. Just as Marx saw the concrete as a product of its
mediations, or internal relations, that were complex and multidimensional, so
too did Nietzsche's multiperspectival approach allow one to analyze phenomena
from different perspectives. Thus, just as Nietzsche championed human and
cultural particularity, so too did he advocate modes of thought that avoid
homogenizing phenomena and that thus cover over their qualitative
particularity.
Nietzsche's
multiperspectival approach undermines claims for absolute truth or for a method
that will guarantee truth and objectivity. Nietzsche was for experimental
science, gaining knowledge through the senses, testing hypotheses and attaining
cumulative knowledge, but he attacked the belief in objectivity, in an
immaculate perception, in a completely non-biased and non-interested mode of
seeing. Perception and cognition were always perspectival, Nietzsche believed,
and he scorned those who believed that science alone attain truth or that the
scientist has privileged access to reality (1967: 146f). Nietzsche also
strongly opposed the mechanistic and scientific view of the world that would
rob it of its aesthetic qualities, scornfully saying: "That the only
justifiable interpretation of the world should be one in which you are
justified because one can continue to work and do research scientifically in your
sense (you really mean, mechanistically?)-- an interpretation that permits
counting, calculating, weighing, seeing and touching, and nothing more -- that
is a crudity and naivete, assuming that it is not a mental illness, an
idiocy" (1974: 335).
Nietzsche's
conception of a multiperspectival discipline led him to question the claims of
science, philosophy, or any one discipline to be the sole road to truth. His
own approach combines many perspectives including philosophy, science, history,
social analysis, aesthetics, and even myth. He himself at various stages
appeared as a philologist, cultural historian and critic, philosopher,
aestheticist and artist, psychologist, and as we are suggesting social
theorist. From this multidisciplinary space, the notion of perspectival
interpretation gives Nietzsche a powerful weapon to criticize the one-sidedness
and reductionism of many forms of modern theory. He appeared before
disciplinary specialization and professionalization appeared and thus provides
a model of a transdisciplinary approach that is able to experiment with
different perspectives and modes of discourse to gain deeper understanding of
the world.
Yet
while arguing for a perspectival way of seeing, Nietzsche is also aware that
sometimes a single strong hypothesis is valuable, claiming that in a modern
"democracy of concepts," "a single concept that wanted to
be master would now be called an ideé fixe. That is our way of
disposing of tyrants -- we direct them to the madhouse" (Nietzsche 1983
[1880]: 369). A single strong and original perspective will obviously
illuminate features missed by those who fail to focus intensely on specifics
and particulars of objects. Indeed, Nietzsche had his own strong and privileged
perspectives that he believed provided unique insights that were of utmost
significance for human life, just as Marx privileged the economic dimension,
providing an original perspective on modern societies.
Contemporary
postmodernists therefore sometimes mistake Nietzsche's perspectivism for an
"anything goes" type of relativism and irrationalism. But this is
precisely the type of intellectual indolence that he despised. Perspectivism
is, instead, a highly disciplined specific mode of thought. Practiced
"modestly" and with a sensitivity to limits, science is itself a
perspectivist resource that provides access to multiple realities, provides
knowledge about specific conditions and particular situations, and challenges
to error and dogma. On these grounds, Nietzsche considered science as a sign of
"a higher multiplicity of culture." After stripping away the
positivist veneer, he praised its "disciplining of the intellect, clarity,
and severity in matters of intellectual conscience, noble coolness and freedom
of the intellect" (Nietzsche 1968b [1889]: 122-126, 162-165, 171-175).
Thus,
Nietzsche did not completely reject the concept of truth as a lie or illusion.
Rather he inquired into the value of truth for life and ruthlessly exposed many
taken-for-granted truths as sublimations of a will to power, thus delineating
the interconnectedness of truth and power. His aphorisms and essays provide
different optics that are sometimes contradictory, but which provide stronger
ways of seeing and understanding than more one-sided, disciplinary optics.
Nietzsche himself is clearly a seeker of truth but dramatically redefined that
search and the nature and value of what was being sought.
Truth
would not be found in the authoritative voice of one privileged perspective,
even his own, but in a dialogue of many perspectives that fully cultivated a
perspectival concept of knowledge. As a philosopher of difference, Nietzsche
was aware that individuals had different perspectives according to their class,
gender, race, and ethnicity and his multiperspectival approach suggests that all
subject positions are necessarily biased and limited and that therefore
dialogue and debate from many positions is more likely to illuminate a
phenomenon than a single perspective. Yet Nietzsche believed that stronger
perspectives would prevail in sustained debate and that one's perspective could
be strengthened in some cases by appropriating one's opponents insights and
taking them to a higher level.
Moreover,
Nietzsche demanded a type of thinking and learning that overcomes the
"indecent haste" and superficiality of modernity. He asserted that:
"One has to learn to learn to think, one has to learn to speak
and write" (Nietzsche 1968b [1889]: 65). He repeatedly stressed the
need to properly digest and assimilate complex thoughts, to make them one's
own. Seeing differences and grasping phenomena from many sides enabled one to
better rank and order phenomena, to see their differences in relationship to
one another, and thus to produce a hierarchy of values and ideals. Nietzsche
was very serious in stressing the importance of "ordering of rank" (Rangordnung),
of producing value hierarchies, and affirming specific values and ideas as
better and more valuable (1968a [1883-1888]: 457ff; 1966 [1886]: 148). Yet the
strong individual, for Nietzsche, recognizes the value of a plurality of
opposing theoretical visions and is able to see things from a multiplicity of
perspectives. Such vision provides a multiplicity of optics on social life and
grasp of contradictory locations, interests, values, strengths, and limitations
of social theories and perspectives.
Nietzsche's
call for a multiperspectival theory thus serves as a critical counterpoint to
general theories that arrogate all of reality to one optic, as well as to
"integrated" approaches that abstractly harmonize irreconcilable
differences and to all theories that abstract from the contradictory
life-worlds from which they arise. Nietzsche thus provides important
methodological contributions to modern theory and should be read, we are
arguing, in the context of 19th century classical social theorists' attempts to
reconstruct social theory in the light of the dynamics of contemporary
societies. Like classical social theorists, Nietzsche carries out a critique of
the limitations of the Enlightenment and earlier modern theory and presents a
counterpoint to more abstract and one-sided theories. In contrast to some of
his contemporary "postmodern" followers, Nietzsche stresses diversity
and plurality, but does not carry out a particularistic and relativistic
undermining of theory. In sharp contrast to the professed aversion to totality
espoused by many contemporary postmodern theorists -- and the sometimes
unspoken rejection of such discourses by empiricists and disciplinary
specialists -- Nietzsche theorized Western culture as a whole and with
normative as well as historical and practical intent. In this regard, he
definitely belongs with the classical social theorists and today's modern
theorists who follow in their tracks.
Deconstructive
and Reconstructive Motifs
Nietzsche
thus emerges in this reading as both a deconstructive and reconstructive
thinker. In the spirit of modernity, Nietzsche deconstructs what he sees as the
oppressive and illusory features of philosophy, morality, religion, and other
modes of thought. He also assaults the irrational, repressive, and massifying
forms of societal normalization and discipline, and thus the rise of a mass
society and culture. Yet he replaces such values (also a modern gesture) with
his own values, philosophy, and positions. Some of Nietzsche's own positions,
such as the theory of perspectivism that we just elucidated are arguably modern
concepts that take modern motifs to higher levels. Some of his own ideals and
positions, however, are anti-modern and even premodern, as we shall see in the
concluding discussion.
The
Enlightenment form of critique is radicalized in Nietzsche and applied to areas
that were neglected by the philosophes and indeed Enlightenment itself is
subject to Nietzsche's withering critical scrutiny. Foreshadowing Adorno and
Horkheimer (1972), Nietzsche sees a sort of dialectic of Enlightenment in which
reason turns into its opposite, becomes myth, but a life-negating one. Reason
is supposed to free the individual from bondage to nature, irrational social
authority, and one's body, but ends up imprisoning individuals in a
life-denying culture.
A
prophetic turn is evident in Nietzsche's thought in Thus Spoke Zarathrustra
(1883-6) in which he adopts a literary form and strategy to present the major
ideas of his later period. While this text is usually read as the key
exposition of Nietzsche's distinctive late philosophy, we also find his
literary master-piece to be an important part of his critique of social and
political modernity, though it also evidences a (re)turn to the sort of
premodern ideals, found in his early celebration of Greek tragedy, the
Dionysian aspects of Greek culture, and its agonistic competition and emphasis
on strong and heroic individuals. His highly prophetic literary text, similar
in style and strategy to cultural modernism, is animated by an impulse to go
beyond the present organization of society, to produce an entirely different
society and culture based on the creativity of strong individuals, which would
be made possible by appropriation of Nietzsche's philosophy. At this stage,
Nietzsche thus sees himself as the great critic of modernity and the sage who
will produce a new culture.[19]
The figure of the Persian sage Zarathrustra in the text is obviously a
mouthpiece for Nietzsche himself and the text articulates his most deeply held
convictions and key ideas.
Yet
the figure of Zarathrustra appropriates a premodern figure as Nietzsche's
mouthpiece, highlighting his deep attachment to ancient philosophies. The form
of Zarathrustra replicates the biblical mixture of teachings, sayings,
songs, and prophecies, though Nietzsche's modernist irony often undercuts the
gravity of biblical discourse. The idea of the eternal recurrence, presented as
the key to Zarathrustra's teaching, also replicates ancient teachings that
everything would eternally recur in a blind wheel of fate, a position held by
certain versions of Zoroastralism.[20]
While this is a premodern idea it is inflected in Nietzsche's vision to help
create the ability to deal with the repetitiveness of modern life and to create
individuals strong enough to bear all suffering, even the most severe type that
would be repeated eternally in Nietzsche's vision.
There
are also anti-modern inflections in Nietzsche's critique of the state in
"The New Idol" where he champions traditional society over the modern
state, with Nietzsche presenting the state as "a cold monster" that
is the "death of peoples" (1954 [1883-1885]: 160). The contrast is
between a "people" with its traditions, "customs and
rights" and the modern state with its lies and pretensions. Nietzsche's
critique of both the marketplace and state takes place from a radically
antimodern individualistic position in Zarathrustra, espousing withdrawal
and isolation over participation and involvement in the key institutions of
modernity: "Foul smells their idol, the cold monster.... break their
windows and leap to freedom" (1954 [1883-1885]: 162). Yet one could read
this doctrine also as part of a drive beyond the limitations of modernity to a
new society and culture without the burden of the modern state.
Along
with Heidegger, one could read Nietzsche's doctrine of the will to power as a
reversion to metaphysics, to the old Greek notion that there was a single
metaphysical key to the universe.[21]
Yet one could also read it as a uniquely modern idea, as an expression of the
growing power of individuals and social forces in modern societies, in which
science, technology, industry, and the new forms of social organization are
creating new forms of power -- forms that would, as Nietzsche and later the
Frankfurt School and Foucault remind us, provide society with new powers over
individuals and individuals with new powers of self-expression and development.
And the modern expansion of power would also lead to imperialist wars which
Nietzsche anticipated.
Nietzsche's
concept of the Ubermensch, the overman, who constitutes a higher form of
human being can also be seen as a typically modern idea, as expressive of the
modern will to development, growth, and innovation. An ancient premodern sage,
Zarathrustra, however, is Nietzsche's chosen figure for the teacher of the Ubermensch
and Nietzsche's championing of the cultural warrior, the noble aristocrat of
the spirit, the sage, and the artist philosopher can be read as a replication
of ancient ideals. Moreover, it is hard to read Nietzsche's ideas of the
eternal recurrence, Amor Fati, and his celebration of Dionysus as anything
other than premodern ideals. Nietzsche's concept of Amor Fati, his affirmation
that "every man is himself a piece of fate" and his arguments for
determinism and fatalism (Nietzsche 1983 [1880]: 325) reveal the lasting
influence of certain Greek ideas on Nietzsche. And his celebration of Dionysus
as a figure of liberation shows his proclivities to premodern thought.
In
his last completed work, Twilight of the Idols (1968b [1889]), one finds
Nietzsche privileging premodern ideals in his attacks on Greek philosophers and
decadent Hellenists in contrast to his celebration of Dionysus "as a means
to understanding the older Hellenic instinct, an instinct still exuberant and
even overflowing: it is explicable only as an excess of energy"
(1968b: 108). Succeeding passages equate the Dionysian with his vitalist ideal:
"For it is only in the Dionysian mysteries, in the psychology of the
Dionysian condition, that the fundamental fact of the Hellenic instinct
expresses itself -- its 'will to life'. What did the Hellene guarantee
to himself with these mysteries? Eternal life, the eternal recurrence of
life: the future promised and consecrated in the past; the triumphant Yes to
life beyond death and change; true life as collective continuation of
life through procreation, through the mysteries of sexuality" (1968b:
109).
The
figure of Dionysus synthesizes Nietzsche's nostalgia for the mysteries of
ancient Greece with his distinctive affirmation of life and life-energies such
as sexuality. Nietzsche feared that modernity was devitalizing individuals and
looked to ancient Greece for ideals of more vibrant life. However, just as
Nietzsche's morality is one-sided in affirming the individual while attacking
social morality, so too is his appropriation of modernity one-sided, affirming
such modern values as individuality, dynamism, and development, while rejecting
the institutions of social and political modernity.
Thus,
Nietzsche's thought contains a unique synthesis of modern and premodern
elements that envisage a postmodern break with modernity. Many of his core
values are premodern, his critiques of religion, philosophy, and morality are
thoroughly modern, as are his celebrations of individuality, free-thinking, and
self-overcoming, while he dreams of a new (postmodern) era that overcomes the
ills and limitations of the present age. Nietzsche is his contradictions
and key contradictions are between the modern and premodern elements in his
thought. Thus, although his thought is, on one hand, thoroughly modern, and
even modernist in its formal qualities, Nietzsche only affirms some modern
ideas while rejecting others. Moreover, he yearns for a higher civilization
that builds on the ancient cultures that he continues to valorize and the most
animate elements of modern culture. From this perspective, the key ideas of his
later philosophy can be read as a series of attempts to create new energizing
myths for the contemporary era. The concepts of the will to power, the Overman,
eternal recurrence, amor fati, Dionysus, and so on can be interpreted as
producing the components of a set of modern myths. Nietzsche, the great scholar
of classical antiquity, saw the power of myth in human life and the need for a
new set of myths for the contemporary era.
On
the other hand, Nietzsche's work aimed at radical disenchantment and creating
higher individuals able to see reality without illusions and to fully develop
their potentials and abilities, thus putting him in a critical Enlightenment
tradition. Consequently, Nietzsche's dual project can be read as an attempt to
create a set of myths that might produce stronger, higher, and more creative
human beings in the contemporary moment and individuals strong enough to do
without myths. Afraid that modernity was devitalizing human beings and robbing
them of their individuality and power of self-determination, Nietzsche sought
emancipatory ideas that would create new and higher individuals. Since
this was a tendency of modernity itself, one can thus read Nietzsche as
replicating certain modern impulses while critiquing other ones, drawing on
some premodern ideals to create a postmodern break, that would be beyond modernity
to yet a higher, better and more life-affirming type of culture and society.
Nietzsche and Modernity: Some Critical
Reflections
On
one hand, Nietzsche articulates some of the deepest core ideas of modernity,
advocating such key values as individualism, growth, development, innovation,
and the destruction of the old and the development of the new. A pathos of the
new permeates his work that sought new beginnings, values, and even a new era
via negation of the old. In his emphasis on self-overcoming and growth,
Nietzsche is similar to the Promethean-Faustian spirit that Marx also
exemplified, a modern rejection of the past and present along with the
development of new values and modes of life. But unlike Marx who developed a
fundamentally scientific discourse for social theory, both the style and
content of Nietzsche's texts deploy the strategies of aesthetic modernism,
exemplifying in form and content Rimbaud's exhortation to changer la vie
and Pound's demand to "make it new." His aphoristic texts are
experimental and philosophize in a new manner. Likewise, Zarathrustra is
a modernist text, finding a new form to express Nietzsche's philosophy.
Throughout
his life, Nietzsche analyzed what he perceived as the problems and ills of the
modern age and would continue to offer cultural solutions to the problems
dissected, unlike Marx who envisaged economic solutions and the reordering of
politics and society as solutions to the ills of modernity. Yet it is important
to note that Nietzsche also envisaged a cultural transformation through the
production of a new culture, although in his later work he would also posit
more individualist solutions. Nietzsche's perspectives on modernity are thus
highly aestheticist and culturalist, seeking cultural transcendence in a new
culture and seeing life-affirming culture as the key to individual and cultural
transformation. His turn toward appropriation of critical Enlightenment
perspectives in his middle writings, however, bring him more into the field of
discourse of classical social theory in which Nietzsche offers novel insights
into contemporary society, culture, and politics.
But
unlike classical social theory, Nietzsche does not engage in substantive
sociological research and has a problematic relationship to the sciences of his
day. On the one hand, Nietzsche calls for new experimental modes of thought and
a new gay science -- more playful,
modest, skeptical, and provisional than the sciences of his day -- thus he is
not hostile to science per se. But Nietzsche engages in more aestheticized and
philosophical modes of discourse than the other classical social theorists and
does not carry out patient sociological investigation and development of his
ideas. Likewise, although his mode of thought is historical -- and while the
early Nietzsche engaged in intense scholarly research into Greek and Roman
culture -- his genealogical method of his middle and later writings tends
toward a sort of armchair historizing, a form of speculative history, and does
not take the more rigorous scholarly form of historical research as found in
social theorists like Marx or Weber at their best.
Put
more polemically, many of Nietzsche's "genealogies" are
pseudo-history based on philosophical speculation and sweeping generalizations
that are often quite dubious from a more rigorous historical perspective. His
historical examples and genealogies are often used to illustrate moral or
philosophical points and this sort of speculative and tendential historicizing
is at odds with later social theory (although, obviously, many social theorists
engage in frequently speculative history and are in their various ways
tendential). Moreover, Nietzsche lacks an institutional analysis of modern
societies and analysis of how the institutions fit together into a modern
social system, as one finds in Marx's and Weber's analyses of capitalist
society. And while he has many insights into how modern societies socialize
women into oppressive roles and behavior, he has no theory of patriarchy, of an
entire mode of social organization that is oppressive of women. Thus, while
there are many important sociological insights in Nietzsche, there is no real
social theory in the sense that maps out how social institutions, relations,
and practices form a social constellation and system.
Nietzsche
also lacks adequate political institutional analysis. His politics are not
really thought out or developed. While he has ideals of stronger individuality
and cultural diversity he has no political analysis of what sort of
institutions could best produce these ideals. Moreover, Nietzsche opposes all
of the liberal and progressive movements of his day that were struggling
against some of the same things that he was criticizing. Unlike Marx, Dewey,
and other progressive theorists who based their hopes for social change on
actually existing movements and social forces -- and who believed that modern
societies contained the resources for their own internal regeneration and
reform, -- Nietzsche thought that change could only come from a cultural
revolution and a negation of the existing modern institutions and social forms
carried out by a cultural elite, but has no vision of an alternative society or
social organization.
Indeed,
Nietzsche has a basically negative concept of the social per se and no positive
social values or ideals. Unlike classical social theorists who believe that the
new modes of social organization in modern societies provide forms of
association, norms, and socio-cultural bases for critique, reform, and
reconstruction of modern societies, Nietzsche believed that modern societies
were hopelessly decadent and incapable of providing resources for their
renewal. Thus, in his view, regeneration would have to come from a radically
new culture which he himself hoped to animate. Yet one could argue that
Nietzsche was weakest precisely where other modern social theorists were
strongest: in providing analysis and inventory of the social resources for
political struggle and social transformation. Any sense of non-repressive
social solidarities is missing in Nietzsche whose hopes are purely
individualistic. Compared with Marx and later social theorists, Nietzsche's
analysis of the modes of organization, institutions, and forms of modern
society ultimately lacks a sense of the positive potentials in social
modernity. Nietzsche thus lacks a language for dealing with forms of
association, social bonds, and the positive potentials for democracy, wider
association and communication, and freer individuality in modern societies.
Moreover,
Nietzsche's low estimation of liberal democracy, feminism, and projects of
social reconstruction like socialism provide little help in detecting and
grasping the shape of democratic aspirations which have percolated from
Nietzsche's time to ours. Part of the problem is that Nietzsche's conception of
morality is also one-sided, limiting itself to individual morality and
eliminating social morality as inherently repressive, leveling, and inimicable
to creativity, the development of a higher individuality and other of
Nietzsche's individualist values. He therefore lacks both a positive
appropriation of the potentials of social modernity and a social ethics to
complement his individualist ethic.
Thus
Nietzsche not only criticizes the massification and homogenization of human
beings (anticipating later critiques of mass society) and the power politics of
the modern state, but rejects the progressive heritage of the bourgeois
revolutions (i.e. democracy, rights, fraternity, and social solidarity), as
well as the progressive movements of the day (socialism, feminism, anarchism,
and so on). The problem with Nietzsche is thus that he fails to affirm key
aspects of social modernity, which he attacks from the standpoint of largely
premodern ideals. Despite his distinctively modern traits and impulses,
Nietzsche is ultimately not modern enough.
Yet
Nietzsche's powerful and provocative critiques are useful in focusing social
theory on the trends toward domination, mediocrity, nationalism, and
massification that modern societies were producing. His critique of the modern
state and democracy forces an illusionless focus on the obstacles to genuine
democracy and the forms of domination present in existing modern societies. His
call for a new form of culture and critique of values highlights the importance
of cultural renewal and a revolution in values in order to realize the deepest
promises of modernity that call for the full development and realization of the
individual.
Nietzsche
was a great detector of modern forms of domination and he deeply influenced
later students of domination such as the Frankfurt school and Foucault.
Further, Nietzsche's calls for an experimental "gay science," his
emphasis on the aesthetic and cultural dimension, and his critiques of
rationality and domination provide an imaginative counterforce to the
tendencies toward formalism, abstraction, quantification, and specialization
that would undermine the power of much later social theory. But although there
are deep aesthetic impulses which run throughout Nietzsche's work, it is a
mistake to accept readings of his life work which reduce him to aestheticism
and to read Nietzsche solely under the sign of aesthetic modernity, as do many
of his contemporary disciples and critics. Instead, one of the most
characteristic marks of his work is a critique of modernity and a series of
attempts to overcome what he considers to be its baleful features which puts
him in the orbit of classical social theory that we are reading as discourses
on modernity. Nietzsche is entwined in the same stream of thought rooted in
Enlightenment discourses and their problems as modern social theory and is
dealing with much of the same subject matter. Certainly, at some stages of his
work Nietzsche celebrated the artist, artistic metaphysics, and aesthetic
modernity as the highest form of life, but the figures of the philosopher, the
experimental thinker, and free spirits are also privileged tropes in his work.
Crucially,
Nietzsche contributed to the climate in which modern society and culture were
viewed and was one of the most influential thinkers of the modern era.
Beginning around 1890 he had an incalculable influence on modernist avant-garde
movements, bohemian subcultures, oppositional political movements, and the
general climate of thought. His influence permeated modern social theory
through his influence on Max Weber and his generation, and it is to that
fateful constellation of ideas that we now turn.
Notes
[1] This is an unpublished book chapter of a study of modernity and modern theory, and I am indebted to Robert J. Antonio for critical comments, discussions, and ideas that helped shape this study.
[2]. The most reliable biographies of Nietzsche include Hollingdale 1965; Hayman 1980; and the three-volume work by Janz 1977, 1978 and 19xx. Kaufmann 1968 [1950] provides a useful introduction to his life, work, and influence.
[3]. For conflicting views of Nietzsche, women, and feminism, see the articles in Patton 1993 and Oliver 1995.
[4]. This same passage appeared verbatim in the two separate texts cited. Since there is as yet no scholarly edition of Nietzsche's works in English, I use the most accessible paperback translations of his works, many of which were edited and translated by Walter Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale and published in relatively inexpensive paperback editions; the date of original publication is in brackets, signaling, in some cases, the various editions prepared by Nietzsche over a several year period by citing multiple years; e.g. 1883-1888 for Thus Spake Zarathrustra.
[5]. Strauss' text greatly influenced the Young Hegelians when it was published in 1835 and intensified the modern philological and philosophical critique of religion begun in the Enlightenment which culminated in Nietzsche himself. Indeed, the Young Hegelians anticipated Nietzsche's critique of religion with Bruno Bauer declaring "God is Dead," Marx describing religion as "the opium of the people," and Feuerbach interpreting religion as the projection of human qualities onto a deity. On the Young Hegelian critique of religion, see Hook 1936 and Lowith 1967 [1940].
[6]. Thomas (1983) analyzes Nietzsche's impact on the Left, counterbalancing Kaufmann's (1950) study of his appropriation by the Right and consequent distortion. Aschheim (1992) demonstrates Nietzsche's appropriation by both progressive and reactionary forces and his tremendous impact on the European socio-political milieu, beginning in the 1890s. Bergman (1987) provides an excellent political contextualization of Nietzsche's work, while Detweiler (1990) contributes a convincing polemic against Kaufmann and others who maintain that Nietzsche was primarily apolitical. We however, offer a different interpretation of Nietzsche's politics from these writers, arguing that Nietzsche's "anti-politics" constituted an often contradictory attack on existing social and political institutions in the name of a higher cultural politics.
[7]. The historical Socrates, of course, was much more intuitive, passionate, aesthetic, and erotic than in Nietzsche's model, but we are arguing that the conception of Socratic culture is an ideal type that crystallizes a model of Greek rationalism in the figure of Socrates and that therefore what is important for our analysis is the model of Socratic culture and its later effects and not whether or not this accurately characterizes the historical Socrates.
[8]. See Nietzsche's meditations on Schopenhauer and Wagner in 1990 [1873-5]. On Nietzsche and Schopenhauer, see Simmel 1991 [1907]). It was under Schopenhauer's influence that Nietzsche could proclaim in The Birth of Tragedy that art is the "essential metaphysical activity" and that "it is only as an aesthetic phenomenon that existence and the world are eternally justified" (Nietzsche 1967 [1872]: 52). Many interpreters claim that Nietzsche continued to affirm this artistic metaphysics (Megill 1985 and Habermas 1987) and in the course of this chapter we contest this reading. We also contest Lukācs' reading (1980 [1954]) of Nietzsche as the continuation of a current of German irrationalism that begins with Schopenhauer, arguing that Nietzsche's thought is much more complex than in these one-sided presentations.
[9]. Habermas (1987: 93, passim) claims that the experiences of aesthetic modernity were crucial formative experiences for Nietzsche and that he continued to affirm primarily aesthetic solutions to the problems of modernity. We see Nietzsche's development and philosophy as far more complex, however; indeed, Habermas fails to engage Nietzsche's discourse on social and political modernity which we shall focus on, and even downplays the importance of Nietzsche's contributions to philosophy. Thus, we ultimately see Nietzsche's aesthetic metaphysics as but a moment of his work, albeit an important one.
[10]. On the concept of "music of the future" in Wagner, see . Nietzsche titled a lecture series On the Future of Our Educational Institutions (187X, 19XX) and spoke of the music and drama of the future in the later part of The Birth of Tragedy (1967 [1872]).
[11]. On the other hand, Nietzsche's attack on foundationalism, universalizing thought, and metaphysics is often taken as beginning a "postmodern" turn in theory through a radical deconstruction of modern theory. Against such readings, we have argued that much of what is taken to be "postmodern" is already present in a tradition of modern thought, which includes the thinkers discussed in this book; see Antonio and Kellner in Dickens and Fontana 1994.
[12]. It should be noted that there is no evidence that Nietzsche read Marx and he obviously had an extremely shallow notion of socialism which was probably derived from reading newspaper accounts of the German Social-Democratic movement, or other socialist parties of the day. Indeed, one finds in Marx himself a critique of the sort of "crude communism" with which Nietzsche identified socialism. Both Nietzsche and Marx attacked institutions and forces which oppressed and alienated individuals and both stood for the full development of individuality. But in the absence of solid knowledge of Marxian theory, Nietzsche equated socialism with a collectivist, radically egalitarian, and anti-individualist politics.
[13]. Indeed, many socialists and radicals read Nietzsche in this way, seeing him as a progressive critic of German nationalism and militarism, the German state, capitalism and mass society; see Thomas 1983 and Aschheim 1992 for documentation.
[14]. Nietzsche was beloved by members of the Frankfurt school (see Adorno and Horkheimer, 1972 [1946]) and postmodern theorists like Foucault (1972 and 1975) precisely because of his powerful critiques of mass culture and society and its homogenizing and normalizing features.
[15]. On Nietzsche and women, see Note 2.
[16]. See Gilman (1983) for many examples of Nietzsche's friendly relations with women and Thomas (1983) and Aschheim (1992) for documentation concerning Nietzsche's positive effect on the feminist movements that emerged after his descent into madness in 1889.
[17]. On the limitations of linguistic communication, see Nietzsche 1968a [1888]: 50, 203-204, 275, 334, 371, 427-428. For similar arguments about the aesthetic and bodily components of communications, see Dewey 1989 [1934]: 275, who we discuss in a later chapter.
[18]. Adorno and Horkheimer applied this multiperspectival method to a study of anti-semitism in Dialectic of Enlightenment (1972), approaching the phenomenon from economic, political, sociological, religious, anthropological, psychoanalytic, and other perspectives.
[19]. This self-image explains how Nietzsche could present himself in his semi-autobiographical Ecce Homo as "dynamite," a "fate," and the great precursor of a new philosophy and culture.
[20]. Cite ER in Zara and sources on doctrines origin; not a modern idea!
[21]. Heidegger interprets Nietzsche as the last metaphysician, claiming that he continues the Western metaphysical practice of seeking a single key to the universe, though he destroys Platonist metaphysics and finds the key to being in the sensory world (Heidegger 1977: 53ff.).