THE
POSTMODERN TURN IN PHILOSOPHY:
By Steven
Best and Douglas Kellner
In the realm of
philosophy and other theoretical discourses, there are many different paths to
the turn from the modern to the postmodern, representing a complex genealogy of
diverse and often divergent trails through different disciplines and cultural
terrains. One pathway moves through an irrationalist tradition from romanticism
to existentialism to French postmodernism via the figures of Nietzsche,
Heidegger, and Bataille into the proliferation of French postmodern theory.
This is the route charted by Jurgen Habermas in The Philosophical Discourse
of Modernity (1987), a trajectory that ultimately leads for him to the dead
end of irrationalism and the catastrophe of fascism.
More positive
narratives of the genealogy of the postmodern turn in theory include Richard
Kearney's journey through the progression of premodern, modern, and postmodern
modes of thought to the triumph of a new postmodern imagination and vision
(1988). Also deeply rooted in aesthetic theory, Ihab Hassan (1987) describes
the outlines of a postmodern culture of "unmaking" that emerges out
of modernism, pragmatism, and changes in modern science that, at its best, will
help advance William James' vision of an "unfinished pluralistic
universe." John McGowan (1991) in turn tells the story of the emergence of
poststructuralist, neoMarxist, and neopragmatist postmodern theories arising
out of the tradition of Kant, Hegel, Marx, and Nietzsche, building on but
overcoming the limitations of their predecessors. Many accounts of the
postmodern turn privilege Nietzsche and Heidegger as key progenitors of the
postmodern turn who generate innovative and critical modes of thought, novel
forms of writing, and emancipatory values (Vattimo 1988; Kolb 1990), providing
a positive spin on the postmodern turn in philosophy.
We show in this
study how assessments of the basic assumptions of modern philosophy by
Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and Heidegger generated provocative postmodern modes of
discourse, writing, and criticism. A group of French thinkers in the 1970s
associated with poststructuralism radicalized the critique of modern philosophy
and became labeled as postmodern theorists (Best and Kellner, 1991). Derrida,
Foucault, Lyotard, Baudrillard, and others developed original and challenging
modes of thought and writing, driving philosophy into novel arenas and topics.
In the 1980s, postmodern theory spread throughout the world and American
thinker Richard Rorty also became associated with the postmodern turn in
philosophy. Rejecting totalizing dismissals of postmodern thought and fervent
affirmations, we adopt a dialectical approach that mediates between modern and
postmodern theory to develop critical theory and politics for the contemporary
era. We argue that while postmodern theory carries out radical critiques and
some productive reconstruction of modern theory and politics, it is vitiated by
its too extreme rejection of normative perspectives and modern theory, and thus
we call for mediation between modern and postmodern discourses.[1]
Modern philosophy
has been largely secular and humanistic, focusing on the abilities of human
beings to discover natural and social truths and to construct their worlds
accordingly. Modern theorists assume that there is order and laws in the cosmos
and society that reason can discover in order to represent and control nature
and social conditions. Reason is deemed the distinctive human faculty, the
cognitive power that would enable humans to dominate nature and create moral
and just societies. Faith in rationality was born in the Renaissance and the
scientific revolutions of the 16th and 17th century, enthroned in the 18th
century Enlightenment, and triumphant, though challenged, by the 19th century.
Key 19th century thinkers like Kierkegaard and Nietzsche, however, questioned
the pretensions of reason and modern theory, thus clearing the way for a
postmodern turn in philosophy.
Danish religious
philosopher Soren Kierkegaard carried out a systematic critique of the
pretensions of reason and an abstract rationalism which he believed that the
modern age was nurturing. Condemning reflection as a "danger" that
ensnares people in logical delays and machinations, Kierkegaard compared it to
a prison. Reflection is for him a form of captivity, a bondage which "can
only be broken by [passionate] religious inwardness" (1978: 81). Reflection
seduces individuals into thinking its possibilities are "much more
magnificent than a paltry decision" (1978: 82). It leads them to act
"on principle," to dwell on the deliberation of the context of their
actions and the calculation of their worth or outcome. Kierkegaard argues that
this drives away feeling, inspiration, and spontaneity, all of which are
crucial for true inner being and a vital relation to God. For Kierkegaard, as
Nietzsche would later agree, genuine inner being (and culture) is characterized
by the tautness and tension of the soul which characterizes passionate
existence. But the "coiled springs of life relationships ... lose their
resilience" in reflection (1978: 78) and "everything becomes
meaningless externality, devoid of [internal] character" (1978: 62).
Kierkegaard thus
contributes to the development of an irrationalist tradition that has echoes in
some later postmodern thought. Kierkegaard might well have agreed with his
contemporary Fyodor Dostoyevsky, who wrote: "An intelligent [reflective]
man cannot seriously become anything ... excessive consciousness is a
disease" (1974: 3, 5). In an age overtaken by rules and regulations,
genuine action -- which Kierkegaard assumes to be subjective and spontaneous --
is frustrated at every turn. Complaining that we are too "sober and
serious" (1978: 71) even at banquets, Kierkegaard bemoans the fact that
even suicides are premeditated (1978: 68)! "That a person stands or falls
on his actions is becoming obsolete; instead, everybody sits around and does a
brilliant job of bungling through with the aid of some reflection and also by
declaring that they all know very well what has to be done" (1978: 73).
Thus, it is passion, not reflection, that guarantees "a decent modesty
between man and man [and] prevents crude aggressiveness" (1978: 62).
"Take away the passion and the propriety also disappears" (1978: 64).
The ambiguity in
the word "passion" may cause some confusion here. To say that the age
and its individuals are "passionless" is not to say there are no
emotions whatsoever, but rather that there is no true spiritual inwardness and
depth, no intensively motivated action and commitment. It suggests that passion
exists only in a simulated, pseudo-form, "the rebirth of passion"
through "talkativeness" (1978: 64). "Chattering" for
Kierkegaard gets in the way of "essential speaking" and merely
"reflects" inconsequential events (1978: 89-99). Hence, in the
present age, emotions -- which in fact are all too pronounced -- have been transformed into negative
forces.[2]
Anticipating Nietzsche's genealogy of the "slave revolt" in morality,
Kierkegaard claims that the "enthusiasm" of the prior age of
Revolution, a "positively unifying principle, has become a vicious
"envy," a "negatively unifying principle" (1978: 81),
a leveling force in its own right insofar as those lacking in talent and
resources want to tear down those who have them.
Both Kierkegaard
and Nietzsche reduce egalitarian politics to herd envy of the strong or noble.
Yet Kierkegaard systematically champions passion over reason. For Kierkegaard,
there are three stages of existence -- the aesthetic, ethical, and religious.
In each of these stages, passion and non-rational components are deemed
superior to rationality. In the aesthetic stage, it is the sensual pleasures of
culinary taste, art, and eroticism that provide the earthly delights of
everyday life, and not the machinations of reason. In the ethical stage,
Kierkegaard valorizes the passion of resolve, choice, and commitment over
universal principles and the faculty of moral judgment. The religious stage,
however, is the highest mode of existence for Kierkegaard, who champions the
infinite passion of the choice of Christian belief, the absurd faith in the
Christian mysteries and paradoxes, and the subjective yearning for salvation
and redemption as the heart and soul of the religious life.
Moreover, truth
is subjectivity for Kierkegaard, who acclaims the subjective passion and
commitment whereby a Christian subject lives in the truth, making it the form
and substance of everyday life. Such existential truths are of far more value
for Kierkegaard than the claims of philosophy and science. In particular,
Kierkegaard mocked Hegel with his pretensions of absolute and objective truth
collected into a totalizing system of knowledge. Likewise, Kierkegaard
ridiculed the guarantees of Enlightenment reason and modern science to provide
infallible methods of securing objective knowledge. Such "truths,"
for Kierkegaard, were of little existential import in contrast to the pleasures
and insights of art, the imperatives of ethical commitment, and the infinite
and inexpressible value of religious redemption.
For Kierkegaard,
the subject was a solipsistic monad, yearning for salvation and infinite
happiness, plagued with anxiety and guilt, obsessed with God and religious
transcendence. The social bonds, community, and forms of association which
modern social theory would valorize as the distinctive achievements of
modernity with modes of social integration, interaction, and social norms were
volatilized into a ghostly aura of the phantom public, leaving the individual
in fear and trembling, alone before God and the passion of religious choice.
Hence, Kierkegaard carries out a critique of reason, reflection, objective
knowledge, and modern thought that would influence the postmodern turn in
philosophy.
Nietzsche shares
Kierkegaard's belief that contemporary thought, morality, and religion are
contributing to the levelling process, but unlike Kierkegaard, who has positive
conceptions of morality and religion, Nietzsche tends to see all existing forms
of morality and religion -- and Christianity in particular -- as repressive of
vital life energies and inimical to individuality. Thus Nietzsche radicalizes
the Enlightenment critique of ideology and like Marx advocates a relentlessly
secular approach to values and theory. Nietzsche’s philosophical critique
mutated into modern existentialism and then postmodern theory, making him a
master theorist of both traditions and a link from existentialism to the
postmodern turn in philosophy. In particular, Nietzsche anticipated later
postmodern theory in his critique of the subject and reason, his deconstruction
of modern notions of truth, representation, and objectivity, his perspectivism,
and his highly aestheticized philosophy and mode of writing.
Nietzsche's
celebration of the Dionysian and his critiques of Socratic reason and later
rationalist Greek tragedy present an attack on figures of Enlightenment
rationality and modern science. Nietzsche later makes it clear that the
Socratic, or "theoretic man," who was the target of his critique in Birth
of Tragedy, stands for modern science and rationality, and in an
"Attempt at a Self-Criticism" of his earlier work, Nietzsche claims
that "it was the problem of science itself, science considered for
the first time as problematic, as questionable," which distinguishes his
position (1967a: 18). Indeed, Nietzsche led the way in questioning the value of
science for life, suggesting that the "will to truth" and scientific
lust for objectivity are masks for a will to power and advancement of ascetic
ideals (1968a). Moreover, although it is often not noted, Nietzsche was one of
the first to attack the organization of modern society and to develop a
critique of modernity.[3]
From his early
writings on, Nietzsche, like Kierkegaard, rails against a life-denying
rationalism and idealist philosophy which champions reason over the passions.
Nietzsche interprets the "subject" as a mere construct, an idealized
sublimation of bodily drives, experiences, and a multiplicity of thoughts and
impulses. This "little changeling," on Nietzsche’s view, this
subject, "is believed in more firmly than anything else on earth,"
but is for him a simple illusion created out of modern desperation to have a
well-grounded identity. Belief in the subject is promoted by the exigencies of
grammar which utilize a subject/predicate form, giving rise to the fallacy that
the "I" is a substance, whereas it is really only a convention of
grammar (Nietzsche 1968b: 37-38). For Nietzsche, "the doer" is
"merely a fiction added to the deed -- the deed is everything"
(1968b: 45). "The subject," he concludes, is thus but a shorthand
expression for a multiplicity of drives, experiences, and ideas.
In the spirit of
Enlightenment, Nietzsche also polemicizes against metaphysics, arguing that it
illicitly generalizes from ideas in one historical epoch to the entirety of
history. Against this form of philosophical universalism, Nietzsche argues
"there are no eternal facts, just as there are no absolute truths.
Consequently, what is needed from now on is historical philosophizing,
and with it the virtue of modesty" (Nietzsche 1986: 13). Castigating
traditional philosophy and values from a critical Enlightenment perspective,
Nietzsche anticipates later postmodern critiques of metaphysics, assailing the
concept of enduring knowledge, the notion of a transcendental world, and
presenting metaphysical thought as a thoroughly obsolete mode of thinking. He
attributes the "metaphysical need," at the heart of philosophies such
as Schopenhauer's, to primitive yearnings for religious consolation for the
sufferings of life and he urges "free spirits" to liberate themselves
and pursue thinking and living experimentally (1986: 8).
Nietzsche's
attack on foundationalism, universalizing thought, and metaphysics thus
undertakes a "postmodern" turn in philosophy through a radical
deconstruction of modern theory. But while deconstructionist philosophies
typically terminate in the No, merely seeking to unravel a positive modern
value system into a heap of disconnected fragments, Nietzsche starts and
finishes with a big Yes, a life-affirming value, deconstructing only to
reconstruct. Moving far away from Schopenhauerian pessimism, back toward a
Greek view of tragedy, toward a Dionysian
view of existence, Nietzsche seeks "a justification of life,
even at its most terrible, ambiguous, and mendacious" (1968a: 521), a
justification found in art, creativity, independence, and the emergence of
"higher types" of humanity.
Yet Nietzsche’s
perspectivism denies the possibility of affirming any absolute or universal
values: all ideas, values, positions, and so on are posits of individual constructs
of a will to power, which are to be judged according to the extent to which
they do or do not serve the values of life, creativity, and strong
individuality. For Nietzsche there are no facts, only interpretations, and he
argues that all interpretation is constituted by the individual’s perspectives
and is thus inevitably laden with presuppositions, biases, and limitations. For
Nietzsche, a perspective is thus an optic, a way of seeing, and the more
perspectives one has at one's disposal, the more one can see, and the better
one can understand and grasp specific phenomena. To avoid limited and partial
vision one should learn "how to employ a variety of perspectives
and interpretations in the service of knowledge" (Nietzsche 1968a: 119).
The concept of
perspectival seeing and interpretation provide Nietzsche with a critical
counter-concept to essentialism: objects do not have an inherent essence, but
will appear differently according to the perspective from which they are viewed
and interpreted and the context in which they appear. He describes his own
"search for knowledge as manifested in the dream of having the
"hands and eyes" of many others and of being "reborn in a
hundred beings" (1974: 215). Cultivating this approach requires learning
to see and interpret -- "habituating the eye to repose, to patience,
to letting things come to it; learning to defer judgement, to investigate and
comprehend the individual case in all its aspects" (Nietzsche 1968b: 65).
This passage
points to another virtue of a perspectival optic: learning to grasp the
specificity and particularity of things. Nietzsche mistrusted the distorting
function of language and concepts which are overly abstract and general, and he
required perspectival seeing and interpretation to grasp the uniqueness of
concrete phenomena. Perspectival seeing allows access to "a complex form
of specificity" (Nietzsche 1968a: 340) which makes possible a more
concrete and complete grasp of the particularities of phenomena. Seeing from
conflicting perspectives also opens people to appreciation of otherness and
difference, and to grasp the uncertain, provisional, hypothetical and
"experimental" nature of all knowledge.
Nietzsche's
Progeny and the Postmodern Turn: From Heidegger Through Derrida
Nietzsche's
legacy is highly complex and contradictory and in retrospect he is one of the
most important and enigmatic figures in the transition from modern to
postmodern thought. His assault on Western rationalism profoundly influenced
Heidegger, Derrida, Deleuze, Foucault, Lyotard, and other postmodern theorists
who broke with modern theory and sought alternative theories. Martin Heidegger,
for instance, combines Nietzsche's radical critique of modernity with nostalgia
for premodern social forms and a hatred of modern technology which he sees as
producing powerful forms of domination. In Being and Time (1962 [1927]),
Heidegger developed Kierkegaard's and Nietzsche's critique of the masses and
mass society through his concept of das Man, the impersonal One, or
They-Self, which dominates "average everyday" being. The They-Self
for Heidegger is a form of tyranny which imposes the thought, tastes, language,
and habits of the mass onto each individual, creating a levelling process, such
that "authentic" individuality demands radical self-differentiation
from others (see Kellner 1973).
The process is facilitated by meditation on death and the contingency
and finitude of human existence, which lends an urgency to creative endeavors.
For the later
Heidegger, the critical focus shifted from the existential structures of
individual existence and modern society to modern technology which generates a Gestell,
a conceptual framework that reduces nature, human beings, and objects to
"a standing reserve," as resources for technical exploitation.
Heidegger renounces modern and technological modes of thought and values in
favor of premodern forms of contemplation and "letting Being be,"
thus rejecting modernity in its totality (1977). Like Nietzsche, he ultimately
harkens back to premodern values and with Ernst Junger, Oswald Spengler, and
others he furthers a German anti-rationalist tradition that ultimately helped
produce fascism, an antimodern culture that Heidegger affirmed and promoted.
Heidegger's
assault on modernity was developed by Foucault and assorted postmodern
theorists, while his attacks on metaphysics and modern thought became central
to Derrida. Heidegger argues that modern subjectivity sets itself up as a
sovereign instrument of domination of the object and that its own forms of
representations of the world are taken as the measure of the real (1977). For
Heidegger, the representational form of modern thought and subsequent
subject/object metaphysics illicitly enthrones the subject as the Lord of Being
and positions individuals into an inauthentic relation with Being. Derrida
radicalizes Heidegger's strike against dualistic metaphysics, while Rorty
(1979) develops Heidegger's account of representation into a critique of
philosophy as the mirror of nature. These ideas would eventually coalesce into
a radical negation of modern philosophy, leading many to call for novel modes
of postmodern thought and writing.
In
the 1960s, various posthumanist and anti-metaphysical discourses emerged under
the rubric of postructuralism and, later, postmodern theory. These movements
were premised on attacks on the
Cartesian subject, Enlightenment views of history, and systemic or
"totalizing" modes of modern thought that sought overarching unities
and continuities in society and history. Although a spate of interesting
thinkers like Gilles Deleuze, Roland Barthes, Jean Baudrillard, and Julia
Kristeva grew out of this ferment, Jacques Derrida, Michel Foucault,
Jean-Francois Lyotard, and Richard Rorty emerged as perhaps the major philosophical
figures in the postmodern turn in philosophy.
These
thinkers were resolute historicists who assailed timeless metaphysical notions
such as "Being" and overturned the Cartesian view of the subject in
different ways, while each taking a version of "the linguistic turn"
(Rorty) in philosophy and social theory. Derrida attacks notions such as
center, totality, and structure (1973, 1976, 1981a and 1981b). For Derrida,
difference is at the heart of everything: language has meaning only through linguistic
chain of differentiations. There is no immediate access to reality, no
transcendental signified not mediated through a socially-constituted
language. In a linguistically-created world of human meaning, there is nothing
but an endless chain of signifiers, or intertextuality.
Central to
Derrida’s thought is the attack on metaphysics. From his perspective, the
entire Western legacy of philosophical thinking is Platonic/metaphysical in
that it seeks to erase time, history, difference, and contingency from the
world. Western philosophy seeks flight to an imaginary realm of pure and
timeless universals, as it attempts to discover foundations for truth and
stable values. Philosophical concepts such as Forms, clear and distinct
ideas, Absolute Knowledge, and the transcendental subject all seek to stop
the dissemination of meaning within a closed system of truth. This repression
of meaning inevitably leads the metaphysical texts of Western philosophy into
paradoxes, contradictions, and incoherencies that are ripe for
deconstruction.
To deconstruct
is not the same as to destroy. Deconstruction attempts to undo logical
contradictions, to overturn rigid conceptual oppositions while releasing new
concepts and meanings that could not be included in the old system. At the
heart of Western metaphysics, for example, Derrida finds the opposition between
speech and writing. This binary logic functions in an illicit way to
establish speech as the means of giving presence to the world, while writing is
deemed derivative and inferior. In Derrida’s sense of grammatology, however,
all production of meaning is writing and subject to the infinite play of
signification. By taking away the transcendental signified and advancing the
concept of differance (language organized around difference and deferred, or
mediated, understandings), Derrida, like Nietzsche, wants to leave us without
transcendental illusions, metaphysical unities, and foundations that constrain
thought and creativity.
Western culture
for Derrida is pervaded by philosophy; its binary modes of thought are
constitutive of its literature, science, morality, and imperialist politics.
Philosophy itself is contaminated by metaphysics and moves of exclusion; to
undo the logic behind the exclusion, to challenge the metaphysical
underpinnings of the culture, is to put in question the culture itself.
Ideology relies on two key metaphysical strategies: it constructs dualisms and
hierarchies, and it seeks an absolute grounding point to derive one thing from
another. Thus, dualisms are not innocent: one term (white/male/Western) is
always privileged over another (person of color/female/non-Western); the
superior term is not possible without contrast to the inferior term. The thrust
of deconstruction clearly is normative and political; it is a protest against
marginalization, the violence that isolates and silences a plurality of voices
in the name of a hegemonic power or authority, inverting the dominant and
valorizing the suppressed.
In this light,
Derrida has taken many positions as an engaged intellectual." He has
attacked apartheid, supported Nelson Mandela, helped start an open university
in Paris, spoken out against human rights abuses, and has addressed feminist
issues. Derrida has publicly proclaimed himself a communist and has at times
linked his work to Marxist concerns (which is not to say he is a Marxist or
deconstruction is Marxist method; see Derrida 1994). He has lashed out against
apolitical interpretations of his work. But from what position can
deconstruction speak, if there is no ground, if everything is indeterminate?
Like Foucault, Derrida has no cognitive means of supporting his own position
and no positive evaluative norms. Rather, his emphasis is on skepticism,
destabilization, uprooting, and overturning.
The
deconstructive emphasis of Derrida, Foucault, Lyotard, Rorty and others
underscores one of the main deficits of postmodern theory the failure to
provide normative resources for ethics and political critique. This creates a strange
paradox, one that Habermas (1987) terms a performative contradiction, whereby the postmodern theorist assails
modern theories and societies, yet renounces the resources to justify the
critique as better, superior, or even accurate. As we see in the following
sections, this problem afflicts key postmodern theorists such as Foucault,
Lyotard, and Rorty.
Foucault’s Critique of Rationality and Modernity
Foucault's works have been extremely influential in all fields of contemporary criticism, inspiring not only the "new historicism," but also innovative research in the areas of the family, sexuality, social regulation, education, prisons, law, and the state.[4] In a series of historical studies on madness and psychiatry, illness and medicine, the human sciences, prisons and punishment, sexuality, and ethics, Foucault redefines the nature of social theory by calling into question conventional assumptions concerning the Enlightenment, Marxism, rationality, subjectivity, power, truth, history, and the political role of the intellectual. Foucault breaks with universalist, foundationalist, dialectical, and normative standpoints and emphasizes principles of contingency, difference, and discontinuity. Adopting a nominalist stance, he dissolves abstract essences and universals such as Reason, History, Truth, or Right into a plurality of specific socio-historical forms.
Foucault challenges traditional disciplinary
boundaries between philosophy, history, psychology, and social and political
theory, as well as conventional approaches to these disciplines. He does not do
"theory" in the modern sense that aims at clarity, consistency,
comprehensiveness, objectivity, and truth; rather he offers fragments,
"fictions," "truth-games," "heterotopias,"
"tools," and "experiments" that he hopes will prompt us to
think and act in new ways. Trying to blaze new intellectual and political
trails, Foucault abandons both liberalism and Marxism and seeks a new kind of
critical theory and politics.
By theorizing
the connections between knowledge, truth, and power, such as emerged in
the domain of the human sciences and are bound up with constitution of
individuals as distinct kinds of subjects, Foucault transforms the history of
science and reason into a political critique of modernity and its various modes
of power which assume the form of "normalization" or
"subjectification." Foucault holds to the Nietzschean view that to be
a "subject" -- that is, to have a unified and coherent identity -- is
to be "subjugated" by social powers. This occurs through a
"deployment" of discourse that divides, excludes, classifies, creates
hierarchies, confines, and normalizes thought and behavior. Hence, toward the
end of his career, Foucault declares that his ultimate project has been not so
much to study power, but rather the subject itself: "the goal of my work
... has been to create a history of the different modes by which, in our
[Western] culture, human beings are made subjects" (1982: 208).
Yet this is a
misleading distinction that signals merely a shift in emphasis rather than
approach, since subjectification is the means through which modern power
operates in Foucault’s later writings. In a series of historical studies,
Foucault analyzes the formation of the modern subject from the perspectives of
psychiatry, medicine, criminology, and sexuality, whereby limit-experiences are
transformed into objects of knowledge. His works
are strongly influenced by an anti-Enlightenment tradition that rejects the
equation of reason, emancipation, and progress. Foucault argues that an
interface between modern forms of power and knowledge served to create new
forms of domination. With thinkers like Sade, Nietzsche, and Bataille, Foucault
valorizes transgressive forms of experience, such as madness, violence, or
sexuality that break from the prison of rationality. Where modern societies
"problematize" forms of experience such as madness, illness, and
sexuality, that is, turn them into governmental problems, into areas of life in
need of control and regulation, Foucault in turn queries the social
construction of problems by uncovering their political motivations and
effects and by challenging their character as natural, necessary, or timeless.
In what he calls a "diagnostic critique" that combines philosophy and
history (1989: 38-39, 73), Foucault attempts to clarify the nature of the
present historical era, to underline its radical difference from preceding
eras, and to show that contemporary forms of knowledge, rationality, social
institutions, and subjectivity are contingent socio-historical constructs of
power and domination, and therefore are subject to change and modification.
Foucault's ultimate task, therefore, is "to produce a shift in
thought so that things can really change" (quoted in O'Farrell 1989: 39).
The goal of Foucault's historico-philosophical studies, as he later came to
define it, is to show how different domains of modern knowledge and practice
constrain human action and how they can be transformed by alternative forms of
knowledge and practice in the service of human freedom. Foucault is concerned
to analyze various forms of the "limit experience" whereby society
attempts to define and circumscribe the boundaries of legitimate thought and
action. The political vision informing Foucault's work foresees individuals
liberated from coercive social norms, transgressing all limits to experience,
and transvaluing values, going beyond good and evil, to promote their own
creative lifestyles and affirm their bodies and pleasures, endlessly creating and
recreating themselves.
Foucault denies
there can be any basis for objective descriptive statements of social reality
or universal normative statements that are not socially conditioned and locally
bound. He tries to show that all norms, values, beliefs, and truth claims are
relative to the discursive framework within which they originate. Any attempt
to write or speak about the nature of things is made from within a
rule-governed linguistic framework, an episteme, that predetermines what
kinds of statements are true or meaningful. All forms of consciousness,
therefore, are socio-historically determined and relative to specific
discursive conditions. There is no absolute, unconditioned, transcendental
stance from which to grasp what is good, right, or true. Foucault refuses to
specify what is true because there are no objective grounds of knowledge; he
does not state what is good or right because he believes there is no universal
standpoint from which to speak. Universal statements merely disguise the will
to power of specific interests; all knowledge is perspectival in character. For
postmodern theorists like Foucault, the appeal to foundations is necessarily
metaphysical and assumes the fiction of an Archimedean point outside of
language and social conditioning.
Habermas (1987)
rightly finds perplexing an approach that raises truth claims while destroying
a basis for belief in truth, that takes normative positions while suppressing
the values to which they are committed. For critique to be justified and
effective, it should preserve standards by which to judge and evaluate, but
Foucault's total critique turns against itself and calls all rational standards
into question.
In dissolving
all social phenomena in the acid bath of power and domination, Foucault
prevents critical theory from drawing crucial distinctions, such as those
"between just and unjust social arrangements, legitimate and illegitimate
uses of political power, strategic and cooperative interpersonal relations,
coercive and consensual measures" (McCarthy 1991: 54). One cannot say, for
example, that one regime of power is any better or worse than another, only
that they are different -- "Another power, another knowledge"
(Foucault 1979: 226).
Since ruling
powers attempt to erase such distinctions, or to present injustice as justice,
falsehood as truth, and domination as freedom, Foucault's position unwittingly
supports the mystifications of Orwellian doublespeak, now more rife than ever
(see Kellner 2001), and blocks the discriminations necessary for social
critique. If there are no standards or right, then, with Thrasymacus and
Hobbes, we can conclude might is as right as anything. There can be no ideology
critique where there is no distinction between true and false, and no social or
moral critique without a distinction between right and wrong. The evaluative
character of Foucault's own work is not any less normative for his refusal to
explicitly confront it. The problem becomes glaring in his later work where he
employs normative terms such as liberty and autonomy, but fails to state what
we should be free for. Foucault's anti-normative stance therefore forces
him into self-defeating value neutrality.
Foucault eschews normative positions in part because he wishes to renounce the role of the universal intellectual who legislates values. For Foucault, the task of the genealogist is to raise problems, not to give solutions; to shatter the old values, not to create new ones. Any stronger, more prescriptive role, Foucault argues, can only augment existing relations of power and reproduce hierarchical divisions between rulers and ruled. But Foucault's error is to confuse provisional normative statements for dogmatic ones, to conflate suggestions to be dialogically debated with finalized creeds to be imposed, to fail to see that universal values can be the products not only of power or ideology but also of consensual, rational, and free choice.[5] Consequently, like most postmodern thinkers, he fails to provide normative grounds for critique and positive ideals, a deficit addressed by Lyotard.
While the early works of Jean-Francois
Lyotard were strongly influenced by phenomenology, Marxism, and Nietzsche, in
the 1980s he carried through a resolute postmodern turn in theory. In many circles, Lyotard is celebrated as the postmodern theorist par excellence.
His book The Postmodern Condition (1984;
orig. 1979) introduced the term to a broad public and has been widely discussed
in the postmodern debates of the last decade. During this period, Lyotard
published a series of books which promote postmodern positions in theory,
ethics, politics, and aesthetics. More than almost anyone, Lyotard has
championed a break with modern theory and methods, while popularizing and
disseminating postmodern alternatives. As a result, his work sparked a series
of intense controversies (see Best and Kellner 1991).
Above all, Lyotard has emerged as the champion of
difference and plurality in all theoretical realms and discourses, while energetically
attacking totalizing and universalizing theories and methods. In The
Postmodern Condition, Just Gaming (1985; orig. 1979), The
Differend (1988; orig. 1983) and a series of other books and
articles published in the 1980s, he called attention to the differences among
the plurality of regimes of phrases which have their own rules, criteria, and
methods. Stressing the heterogeneity of discourses, Lyotard argues, following
Kant, that such domains as theoretical, practical, and aesthetic judgement have
their own autonomy, rules, and criteria. In this way, he rejects notions of
universalist and foundationalist theory, as well as claims that one method or
set of concepts has privileged status in such disparate domains as philosophy,
social theory, or aesthetics. Arguing against what he calls terroristic and
totalitarian theory, Lyotard thus resolutely champions a plurality of
discourses and positions against unifying theory.
In The
Postmodern Condition, Lyotard turns affirmatively
to postmodern discourse and sharpens his polemical attack against the
discourses of modernity while offering new postmodern positions. In particular,
he attempts to develop a postmodern epistemology which will replace the
philosophical perspectives dominated by Western rationalism and instrumentalism.
Subtitled A Report on Knowledge, the
text was commissioned by the Canadian government to study
the condition of knowledge
in the most highly developed societies. I have decided to use the word postmodern
to describe that condition. The word is in current use
on the American continent among sociologists and critics; it designates
the state of our culture following the transformations which, since the end of
the nineteenth century, have altered the game rules for science, literature,
and the arts (Lyotard 1984: p. xxiii).
Following our distinctions between postmodernity as a
sociohistorical epoch, postmodernism as a configuration of art after/against
modernism, and postmodern knowledge as a critique of modern epistemology (Best
and Kellner 1991 and 1997), it would be more accurate to read Lyotard’s text as
a study of conditions of postmodern knowledge, rather than of the postmodern
condition tout court, for the text does not
provide an analysis of postmodernity, but rather compares modern and postmodern
knowledge. Indeed, like Foucault, Lyotard carries out a critique of modern
knowledge and calls for new knowledges, rather than developing analyses of postmodern
forms of society or culture.
Consistent with his postmodern epistemology, he never
theorizes modernity as a historical process, limiting himself to providing a
critique of modern knowledge. Thus modernity for Lyotard is identified with
modern reason, Enlightenment, totalizing thought, and philosophies of history.
Failing to develop analyses of modernity and postmodernity, these notions are
undertheorized in his work and shifts postmodern theory away from social
analysis and critique to philosophy. Lyotard thus carries through a linguistic
and philosophical turn which renders his theory more and more abstract and
distanced from the social realities and problems of the present age.
For Lyotard, there are three conditions for modern
knowledge: the appeal to metanarratives to legitimate foundationalist claims;
the inevitable outgrowth of legitimation, delegitimation, and exclusion;
and a desire for homogeneous epistemological and moral prescriptions.
Postmodern knowledge, by contrast, is against metanarratives and
foundationalism; it eschews grand schemes of legitimation; and it is for
heterogeneity, plurality, constant innovation, and pragmatic construction
of local rules and prescriptives agreed upon by participants. The postmodern
condition therefore involves developing an alternative epistemology which
responds to new conditions of knowledge. The main focus of the book accordingly
concerns the differences between the grand narratives of traditional philosophy
and social theory, and what Lyotard calls postmodern knowledge, which he
defends as preferable to modern forms of knowledge.
To legitimate their positions, Lyotard claims
that modern discourses appeal to
metadiscourses such as the narrative of progress and emancipation, the
dialectics of history or spirit, or the inscription of meaning and truth.
Modern science, for instance, legitimates itself in terms of an alleged
liberation from ignorance and superstition, as well as the production of truth,
wealth and progress. From this perspective, the postmodern is defined as
incredulity toward metanarratives, the rejection of metaphysical philosophy,
philosophies of history, and any form of totalizing thought -- be it
Hegelianism, liberalism, Marxism, or positivism.
Lyotard believes that the metanarratives of modernity
tend toward exclusion and a desire for universal metaprescriptions. The
scientist, for instance, provides a paradigmatic example of modernity’s
propensity toward exclusion, as he/she rules out in advance anything that does
not conform to formalizable or quantifiable knowledge (1984: p. 80). Lyotard
argues that the modern act of universalizing and homogenizing metaprescriptives
violates what he considers the heterogeneity of language games. Furthermore, he
claims that the act of consensus also stifles heterogeneity and imposes
homogeneous criteria and a false universality.
By contrast, Lyotard champions dissensus over
consensus, diversity and dissent over conformity and consensus, and heterogeneity
and the incommensurable over homogeneity and universality. He writes:
Consensus does violence to the heterogeneity of language games. And invention
is always born of dissension. Postmodern knowledge is not simply a tool of the
authorities; it refines our sensitivity to differences and reinforces our
ability to tolerate the incommensurable (1984: p. 75).
Knowledge is produced, in Lyotard’s view, by dissent,
by putting into question existing paradigms, by inventing new ones, rather than
assenting to universal truth or agreeing to a consensus. Although Lyotard’s
main focus is epistemological, he also implicitly presupposes a notion of the
postmodern condition, writing: Our working hypothesis is that the status of
knowledge is altered as societies enter what is known as the postindustrial age
and culture enters what is known as the postmodern age (1984: p. 3). Like
Baudrillard, Lyotard thus associates the postmodern with the trends of
so-called postindustrial society. Postmodern society is for Lyotard the
society of computers, information, scientific knowledge, advanced technology,
and rapid change due to new advances in science and technology. Indeed, he
seems to agree with theorists of postindustrial society concerning the primacy
of knowledge, information, and computerization -- describing postmodern
society as the computerization of society.
Yet the
concept of the postmodern condition, we would argue, points to some
fundamental aporia in Lyotard and other French postmodern theories. His war on
totality rejects totalizing theories which he describes as master narratives
that are somehow reductionist, simplistic, and even terroristic by providing
legitimations for totalitarian terror and suppressing differences in
unifying schemes. Yet Lyotard himself is advancing the notion of a postmodern
condition which presupposes a dramatic break from modernity. Indeed, does not
the very concept of postmodernity, or a postmodern condition, presuppose a
master narrative, a totalizing perspective, which envisages the transition from
a previous stage of society to a new one? Doesn’t such theorizing presuppose
both a concept of modernity and a notion of a radical
break, or rupture within history, that leads to a totally new condition which
justifies the term postmodern? Therefore, does not
the very concept postmodern seem to presuppose both a master narrative and
some notion of totality, and thus periodizing and totalizing thought --
precisely the sort of epistemological operation and theoretical hubris which
Lyotard and others want to renounce?
Against Lyotard, we might want to distinguish between
master narratives that attempt to subsume every particular, every specific
viewpoint, and every key point into one totalizing theory (as in Hegel, some
versions of Marxism, or Talcott Parsons) from grand narratives which
attempt to tell a Big Story such as the rise of capital, patriarchy, or
colonialism. Within grand narratives, we might want to distinguish as well
between metanarratives that tell a story about the foundation of knowledge and
the narratives of social theory that attempt to conceptualize and interpret a
complex diversity of phenomena and their interrelations, such as male
domination or the exploitation of the working class. We might also distinguish
between synchronic narratives that tell a story about a specific society at a
given point in history, and diachronic narratives that analyze historical
change, discontinuities, and ruptures. Lyotard tends to lump all large
narratives together and thus does violence to the diversity of narratives in
our culture.
In fact, Lyotard is caught in another double bind
vis-à-vis normative positions from which he can criticize opposing positions.
His renunciation of general principles and universal criteria preclude
normative critical positions, yet he condemns grand narratives, totalizing
thought, and other features of modern knowledge. This move catches him in
another aporia, whereby he wants to reject general epistemological and
normological positions while his critical interventions presuppose precisely
such critical positions (such as the war on totality).
In our view, a more promising venture would be to make explicit, critically discuss, take apart, and perhaps reconstruct and rewrite the grand narratives of social theory rather than to just prohibit them and exclude them from the terrain of narrative. It is likely -- as Fredric Jameson argues (1981) -- that we are condemned to narrative in that individuals and cultures organize, interpret, and make sense of their experience through story-telling modes (see also Ricoeur 1984). Not even a scientistic culture could completely dispense with narratives and the narratives of social theory will no doubt continue to operate in social analysis and critique in any case (Jameson 1984: p. xii). If this is so, it would seem preferable to bring to light the narratives of modernity so as to critically examine and dissect them, rather than to simply prohibit certain sorts of narratives by Lyotardian Thought Police.
It appears that when one does not specify and
explicate the specific sort of narratives of contemporary society involved in
one’s language games, there is a tendency to make use of the established
narratives at one’s disposal. For example, in the absence of an alternative
theory of contemporary society, Lyotard uncritically accepts theories of
postindustrial society and postmodern culture as accounts of the
present age (1984: pp. 3, 7, 37, passim). Yet he presupposes the validity of
these narratives without adequately defending them and without developing a
social theory which would employ political economy and critical social theory
to delineate the transformations suggested by the post in postindustrial or
postmodern. Rejecting grand narratives, we believe, simply covers over the
theoretical problem of providing a narrative of the contemporary historical
situation and points to the undertheorized nature of Lyotard’s account of the
postmodern condition. This would require at least some sort of large narrative
of the transition to postmodernity -- a rather big and exciting story one would
think (see Best and Kellner 2001).
In a sense, Lyotard’s celebration of plurality replays
the moves of liberal pluralism and empiricism. His justice of multiplicities
is similar to traditional liberalism which posits a plurality of political
subjects with multiple interests and organizations. He replays tropes of
liberal tolerance by valorizing diverse modes of multiplicity, refusing to
privilege any subjects or positions, or to offer a standpoint from which one
can choose between opposing political positions. Thus he comes close to falling
into a political relativism, which robs him of the possibility of making
political discriminations and choosing between substantively different
political positions, institutions, and social systems.
Lyotard’s emphasis on a multiplicity of language games
and deriving rules from specific and local regions is similar in some respects
to an empiricism which rejects macrotheory and analysis of hegemonic structures
of domination and oppression. Limiting discourse to small narratives would prevent
critical theory from making broader claims about structures of domination or to
legitimate critical claims made about society as a whole. His wonderment at
the variety of language games and exhortation to multiply discourses, to
produce more local narratives and languages, also replicates the current trend
in academia to multiply specialized languages, to produce a diversity of new
jargons. In fact, postmodern discourses themselves can be interpreted as an
effect of a proliferating intellectual specialization and imperative to produce
ever new discourses for the academic market. Against such theoretical
specializations, we advocate the production of a common, vernacular language
for theory, critique, and radical politics that eschews the jargon and obscurity
that usually accompanies the production of specialized languages. This position
is also advanced by Richard Rorty, although in a form that ultimately rejects
theory.
In theorizing the
postmodern, one inevitably encounters the postmodern assault on theory, such as
Lyotard's and Foucault's rejection of modern theory for its alleged totalizing
and essentializing character. The argument is ironic, of course, since it
falsely homogenizes a heterogeneous "modern tradition" and since
postmodern theorists like Foucault, Lyotard, and Baudrillard are often as
totalizing as any modern thinker (Kellner 1989 and Best 1995). But where
Lyotard seeks justification of theory within localized language games, arguing
that no universal criteria are possible to ground objective truths or universal
values, Foucault steadfastly resists any efforts, local or otherwise, to
validate normative concepts and theoretical perspectives. For Foucault, justification
ensnares one in metaphysical illusions like "truth" and the only
concern of the philosopher-critic is to dismantle old ways of thinking, to
attack existing traditions and institutions, and to open up new horizons of
experience for greater individual freedom. What matters, then, is results, and
if actions bring greater freedom, the theoretical perspectives informing them
are "justified." From this perspective, theoretical discourse is seen
not so much as "correct" or true," but as
"efficacious," as producing positive effects.
Continuing along
this path, postmodernists have attacked theory per se as at best irrelevant to
practice and at worst a barrier to it. Rorty assails both metatheory --
reflection on the status of theory itself which often is concerned with
epistemological and normative justification of claims and values -- and theory,
which he critiques in three related ways that emerge through his own
articulation of the "end of philosophy" thesis. Rigorously trained in
analytic philosophy, Rorty became turncoat and abandoned the professional dogma
that philosophy was "queen of the sciences" or the universal arbiter
of values whose task was to provide foundations for truth and value claims.
Philosophy has no special knowledge or truth claims because it, like any other
cultural phenomenon, is a thoroughly linguistic phenomenon. For Rorty, language
is a poetic construction that creates worlds, not a mirror that reflects
"reality," and there are no presuppositionless or neutral truths that
evade the contingencies of historically shaped selfhood. Consequently, there is
no non-circular archimedean point for grounding theory. Language can only
provide us with a "description" of the world that is thoroughly
historical and contingent in nature.
Thus, the first
move in Rorty's assault on theory is an attack on the idea that theory can
provide objective foundations for knowledge and ethics. Alleged universal
truths are merely local, time-bound perspectives and masks for a
"Real" that cannot be known. The second critique immediately follows:
if there are no universal or objective truths, no neutral language to arbitrate
competing claims, then "theory" has no power to adjudicate among
competing languages or descriptions, a task which inevitably transforms theory
into metatheory once the conditions of argumentation themselves become
sufficiently problematic.
Hence, Rorty
denies that the theorist can definitively criticize, argue, evaluate, or even
"deconstruct," since there is no fulcrum from which to push one claim
as "right," "correct," or "better" than another.
The theorist is replaced by the ironist, one who is aware of the ineliminable
contingency of selfhood and discourse. Accepting the new limitations, the
ironist can only "redescribe" the older theories in new languages and
offer new descriptions for ourselves and others. We adopt values and ideologies
on emotive rather than rational grounds. Every vocabulary is incommensurable
with another and there is no "final vocabulary" with which one can
arbitrate normative and epistemological claims. Thus, for Rorty:
The method is to redescribe lots and
lots of things in new ways, until you have created a pattern of linguistic
behavior which will tempt the rising generation to adopt it ... This sort of
philosophy does not work piece by piece, analyzing concept after concept, or
testing thesis after thesis. Rather it works holistically and pragmatically. It
says things like `try thinking of it this way' -- or more specifically, `try to
ignore the apparently futile traditional questions by substituting the
following new and possibly interesting questions.' It does not pretend to have
a better candidate for doing the same old things which we did when we spoke in
the old way ... Conforming to my own precepts, I am not going to offer
arguments against the vocabulary I want to replace. Instead, I am going to try
to make the vocabulary I favor look more attractive by showing how it may be
used to describe a variety of topics" (1989: 9).
One would think
this replacement of epistemological criteria of truth with aesthetic values
of attractiveness would commit Rorty to relativism, but he denies the term on
the grounds that it belongs to a discredited foundationalist framework, as the
term "blasphemy" makes no sense within an atheistic logic. Whether or
not we can say Rorty is a relativist in the sense of someone who cannot
demonstrate one viewpoint is more true than another, he is not a
"relativist" in the sense of someone who thinks all claims are
equally good or viable. Clearly, Rorty is pushing for some descriptions --
those that celebrate contingency, irony, solidarity, and liberal values -- over
others, but he claims that one cannot "argue" for the new
description. On this level, the attack on theory means simply that it is
useless to provide arguments for one's positions; the only thing one can do is
to offer new descriptions and hope others will find them appealing and more
useful for (liberal) society. Dethroning philosophy, Rorty claims that
literature is a far more powerful mode of interpreting the world and offering
the descriptions needed for self-creation and social progress. Fiction takes
the place of theory. Of course, Rorty cannot help but argue for his positions,
and is himself still writing philosophy not fiction.
From this step
follows the third argument in Rorty's attack on theory. The
"theorist" should abandon all attempts to radically criticize social
institutions. First, as we have seen, "critique" has no force for
Rorty and, ultimately, one description is as good as any other. But
"theory" on this level also means for Rorty the attempt, classically
inscribed in Plato's Republic, to merge public and private concerns, to
unite the private quest for perfection with social justice. Here, Rorty is guided
by the assumption that tradition and convention are far more powerful forces
than reason in the social construction of life, in holding the "social
glue" together.
Rorty holds that
philosophical views on topics such as the nature of the self or the meaning of
the good life are as irrelevant to politics as are arguments about the
existence of God. He wants to revive liberal values without feeling the need to
defend them on a philosophical level: "What is needed is a sort of
intellectual analogue of civic virtue -- tolerance, irony, and a willingness to
let spheres of culture flourish without worrying too much about their `common
ground,' their unification, the `intrinsic ideals' they suggest, or what
picture of man they `presuppose'" (1989: 168). Since philosophy can
provide no shared or viable foundation for a political concept of justice, it
should be abandoned, replaced with historical narratives and poetic
descriptions. Ultimately, Rorty's goal is to redescribe modern culture and the
vocabulary of Enlightenment rationalism in strongly historicist and pragmatist
terms.
In this vein, Rorty’s recent Achieving
Our Country (1998) provides a provocative critique of the academic/cultural
studies Left in the United States. Seeking liberal politics without
(metaphysical) liberal theory and a pragmatic oriented politics rooted in a
strong vision of social reform without the need for theoretical justification,
Rorty asks the Left to get over its obsession with theory and cultural
politics. He demands that the Left kick its philosophy habit, and return to
the kind of politics practiced by an earlier Left, of the Great Depression
period, that was concretely wedded to social reform. Until such concrete
progressive reforms are attained, Rorty maintains, our country remains
unachieved (1998).
Taking a giant
leap to the right of Foucault, Rorty claims not only that philosophy provides
no foundation for politics, it plays no political role whatsoever. Despite his
assault on foundationalism, Foucault was a tireless militant and "engaged
intellectual" who used theory as a weapon for political struggle. For
Rorty, however, philosophy has no public or political role. Reviving the
classic liberal distinction between the public and private, Rorty claims philosophy
should be reserved for private life, where it can be ironic at best, while
leaving political and moral traditions to govern public life. Even Derrida,
master of subversion and irony, insisted that deconstruction entails political
commitments and at least made public and political gestures, however vague or
dilatory.
We
agree with Rorty's initial premise that consciousness, language, and
subjectivity are historical and contingent in nature, that our relation to the
world is mediated many times over, but we reject most of his conclusions.
First, although we too are against foundationalism, we hold that it is possible
for theory to construct non-arbitrary grounds to assess competing factual and
value claims. These grounds are not metaphysical or ahistorical, they are found
in the criteria of logic and argumentation which are reasonable to hold, and in
shared social values that are the assumptions of a liberal democracy which
Rorty himself affirms. Rejecting the implication of Rorty's position, we do not
find it arbitrary to say racism is wrong, or that critiques of racism or sexism
are merely good "descriptions" with which we hope others would agree.
Rather, we find the arguments for racism far weaker than the arguments against
racism and counter to liberal values that enlightened citizens hold -- or
should hold. The assumptions of these anti-racist arguments are of course
themselves historical; they stem from the modern liberal tradition that
proclaims the rights of all human beings to a life of freedom and dignity.
Rorty would rightly see this as a "tradition," but it is one that was
constituted with a strong rational component and has compelling force for those
who wish -- and clearly not all do -- to play the "language game" of
democratic argumentation.
Similarly, while
we do not know what the nature of the universe ultimately is, we find that
astronomy provides a better "description" than astrology, that
evolutionary theory is more compelling that creationism. Our court of appeal is
reason, facts, verified bodies of knowledge, and our experience of the world
itself, which is not infinitely malleable to any and all descriptions, such as
the one which says the earth is flat. Symptomatic of this problem, Rorty adopts
a problematic consensus theory of truth which holds that "truth"
emerges from free discussion; it is "whatever wins in a free and open
encounter" (1989: 67). This ignores the fact that even the
"freest" inquiry can still produce falsehood and that might often
continues to make right. Needless to say, the defense of such claims will
require the tools of theory -- science or philosophy -- rather than fiction.
Abandoning these tools, the ironist is disburdened of the need to defend one's
claims and tries to evade argumentative responsibilities in ways we don't
tolerate in our undergraduate students. For Rorty, "Interesting philosophy
is rarely an examination of the pros and cons of a thesis" (1989: 9).
Admittedly, argumentation is difficult and not always sexy, especially to the
mind of an impatient aestheticist who seeks beauty, novelty, and speed over
rigor, fairness, and coherence. Rorty is only one step away from Baudrillard,
the self-proclaimed "intellectual terrorist" who prefers simply to
blow up ideas with unsubstantiated claims and outrageous exaggerations rather
than attending to matters of evaluating truth or falsehood, or patient
empirical demonstration of his claims (see Kellner 1989).
Moreover, without
some kind of metatheory, Rorty cannot plausibly claim that liberalism is good
or convincingly show which practices are to be favored over others. If politics
is strictly an aesthetic affair, what standards do we use to judge success from
failure, good from bad politics? With Lyotard, Rorty seeks to proliferate ever
new descriptions of the self and the world. This has the value of overcoming
stale assumptions and entrenched dogmas, but it represents a fetishism of
novelty over concern for truth and justice. On this scheme, there can be no
gradual progress toward greater insight and knowledge, there is only succeeding
and random points of discontinuity that scatter inquiry and knowledge in
fragmented directions. Put in Rorty's own terms, our claim is that
foundationalism, rationalism, and progressivist narratives of Western theory
can be "redescribed" in better ways that make them more effective
tools for historical analysis and social critique.
From
our denial that theory is powerless to seek grounds of justification for
claims, or to effectively challenge, counter, refute, or argue for specific
positions, we hold that a crucial role of theory is to step beyond the
circumscribed boundaries of individuality to assess the ways in which the
social world shapes subjectivity. For Rorty, by contrast, the personal is no
longer political. The question, of course, is not whether or not one should be
theoretical, since all critical, philosophical, or political orientations are
theoretical at least in their embedded assumptions that guide thought and
action. No one hoping to speak intelligibly about the world can hope to avoid
theory; one can either simply assume the validity of one's theory, or become
reflexive about the sources of one's theoretical position, their compatibility,
their validity, and their effects. The potential weakness and triviality of a non-theoretical
approach is evident, for example, in the anti-theoretical biases of much
cultural studies that mindlessly celebrate media culture as interesting, fun,
or meaningful, while ignoring its economic, socio-political, and ideological
functions.
Theory is
necessary to the extent that the world is not completely and immediately
transparent to consciousness. Since this is never the case, especially in our
own hypercapitalist culture where the shadows flickering on the walls of our
caves stem principally from television sets, the corporate-dominated ideology
machines that speak the language of deception and manipulation. As we show in
our book The Postmodern Adventure (Best and Kellner, 2001), which
contains studies of Thomas Pynchon, Michael Herr, Mary Shelley, H.G. Wells,
Philip K. Dick, and other imaginative writers, Rorty is right that fiction can
powerfully illuminate the conditions of our lives, often in more concrete and
illuminating ways than theory. Ultimately, we need to grant power to both
theory and fiction, and understand their different perspectives and roles. For
just as novels like Upton Sinclair's The Jungle had dramatic social
impact, so too has the discourse of the Enlightenment, which provided the
philosophical inspiration for the American and French Revolutions, as well as
numerous succeeding revolts in history.
Postmodern
attacks on theory are part and parcel of contemporary misology -- the hatred of
reason -- that also manifests itself in the mysticism pervading some versions
of deep ecology and ecofeminism, in anti-humanist attacks from
"biocentric" viewpoints that often see human beings as nothing more
that a scourge on nature, in the layperson's rejection of philosophy for common
sense, in the pragmatist celebration of the technological and practical, in the
postmodern embrace of desire and spontaneity over reflection, and in the
mindless "spiritualism" pervading our culture (see Boggs 2000:
166ff.). The positive value of pragmatic critiques of theory is to remind one
to maintain a close relationship between theory and practice, to avoid
excessively abstract analyses and becoming mired in a metatheory that becomes
obsessed with the justification of theory over its application -- a problem that frequently plagues
Habermas' work (see Best 1995). The pragmatic critique helps keep theory from
becoming an esoteric, specialized discourse manipulated and understood only by
a cadre of academic experts. No doubt we are not alone in our dissatisfaction
with the highly esoteric discourse that comes not only from modernists like
Habermas, but also -- and more so -- from poststructuralist and postmodern
champions of the ineffable and unreadable, or the terminally obscure and
pompous.
Operating in the
tradition of critical theory, we believe that the role of theory is to provide
weapons for social critique and change, to illuminate the sources of human
unhappiness and to contribute to the goal of human emancipation. Against
Rorty's very unpostmodern dichotomization of the public and private (a
centerpiece of bourgeois ideology), we believe that the citizens of the
"private realm" (itself a social and historical creation) have strong
obligations to participate actively in the public realm through rational
criticism and debate. With Rorty, we do not believe the theorist must seek to
construct a perfect bridge between the public and the private, for the range of
action and choice on the part of the individual always exceeds the minimal
requirements of order in a free society. Rather, the role of the theorist is to
help analyze what the conditions of freedom and human well-being might be, to
ask whether or not they are being fulfilled, and to expose the forces of
domination and oppression.
We see public
intellectuals as specialists in critical thinking who can employ their skills
to counter the abuses of the public realm, in order to help reconstitute
society and the polity more democratically. This involves helping to ensure
that the private realm and its liberties and pleasures are not effaced through
the ever-growing penetration of mass media, state administration, electronic
surveillance, the capitalist marketplace, and globalization. Indeed, new media
and computer technologies have created novel public spheres and thus unique
opportunities for public intellectuals to exercise their skills of critique and
argumentation (Kellner 1997).
In addition, we
believe that theory can provide social maps and historical narratives
which supply spatial and temporal contextualizations of the present age. Social
maps study society holistically, moving from any point or mode of human
experience into an ever-expanding macroscopic picture that may extend from the
individual self, to its network of everyday social relations, to its more
encompassioning regional environment, to its national setting, and finally to
the international arena of global capitalism. Within this holistic framework,
social maps shift from one level to another, articulating complex connections
between economics, politics, the state, media culture, everyday life, and
various ideologies and practices.
Historical
narratives, similarly, contextualize the present by identifying both how the
past has constituted the present and how the present opens up to alternative
futures. As argued in the historicist tradition that began in the nineteenth
century -- in the work of Hegel, Dilthey, Marx, Weber, and others -- all
values, worldviews, traditions, social institutions, and individuals themselves
must be understood historically as they change and evolve through time. As in
the form of Foucault's genealogies or various popular histories, historical
narratives chart the temporal trajectories of significant experiences and
events, of political movements, or the forces constituting subjectivities.
Against the postmodern tendency to randomize history as a disconnected series
of events, we believe historical narratives should grasp both historical
continuities and discontinuities, while analyzing how continuities embody
developmental dynamics, such as moral and technical evolution, that have
emancipatory possibilities and should be further developed in the future (Best
and Kellner 1991, 1997, 2001).
Together, social
maps and historical narratives study the points of intersection between
individuals and their cultures, between power and knowledge. To the fullest
degree possible, they seek to lift the veils of ideology and expose the given
as contingent and the present as historically constituted, while providing
visions of alternative futures. Maps and narratives, then, are meant to
overcome quietism and fatalism, to sharpen political vision, and to encourage
translation of theory into practice in order to advance both personal freedom
and social justice. Social maps and historical narratives should not be
confused with the territories and times they analyze; they are approximations
of a densely constituted human world that require theory and imagination. Nor
should they ever be seen as final or complete, since they must be constantly
rethought and revised in light of new information and changing situations.
Finally, as we are suggesting, these maps can deploy the resources of either
"theory" or "fiction," since both provide illuminations of
social experience from different vantage points, each of which are useful and
illuminating, and necessarily supplement each other.
The social maps
called classical social theories are to some extent torn and tattered, in
fragments, and in some cases outdated and obsolete. But we need to construct
new ones from the sketches and fragments of the past to make sense of our
current historical condition dominated by media culture, information explosion,
new technologies, and a global restructuring of capitalism. Maps and theories
provide orientation, overviews, and show how parts relate to each other and to
a larger whole. If something new appears on the horizon, a good map will chart
it, including sketches of some future configurations. And while some old maps
and authorities are discredited and obsolete, some traditional theories
continue to provide guideposts for current thought and action, as we have
attempted to demonstrate in our various books that marshall both modern and
postmodern theories to map and narrativize our present moment (see Best and
Kellner 1997 and 2001).
Yet we also need
new sketches of society and culture, and part of the postmodern adventure is
sailing forth into new domains without complete maps, or with maps that are
fragmentary and torn. Journeys into the postmodern thus thrust us into novel
worlds, making us explorers of uncharted, or poorly charted, domains. Our
mappings can thus only be provisional, reports back from our explorations that
require further investigation, testing, and revision. Yet the brave new worlds
of postmodern culture and society are of sufficient interest, importance, and
novelty to justify taking chances, leaving the familiar behind, and trying out
new ideas and approaches.
Critical theories
require a standpoint for critique and thus normative dimensions. As we have
argued elsewhere (Best and Kellner 1991 and 1997), normative concepts and
values like democracy, freedom, social justice, human rights, and other value
heritages of modern society were themselves validated in theoretical
discussions and political struggles and provide important standpoints of
critique. Normative critique, therefore, does not necessarily involve
foundational or universalist positions, nor is it merely subjective and
arbitrary. Rather cultures and societies over long periods of history have come
to agree that certain values, institutions, and forms of social life are
valuable enough to struggle and die for and one of the tasks of critical theory
is to explicate and defend which normative positions continue to be relevant and
vital in the contemporary era.
Finally, we need
new politics to deal with the problems of capitalist globalization,
environmental crises, species extinction, terrorism, and the failure of
conventional politics to provide social justice and well-being for all. We fear
that just as Rorty's and other postmodernist’s assaults on theory block
attempts to map and critique the new social constellations of the present
moment, so too do attacks on radical politics and defense of a reformist
liberalism and pragmatism vitiate attempts to deal with the new global forces
of technocapitalism. Demonstrations against the World Trade Organization
meetings in Seattle in December 1999 and the subsequent anti-globalization
movement (see Best and Kellner, 2001) suggest that the radical spirit is still
very much alive. Indeed, we believe that it is new social movements and the
forces of radical opposition which provide the most promising avenues of
radical democratic social transformation in the present moment.[6]
Thus, while postmodern
approaches offer much to the reconstruction of critical theory and democratic
politics for the present age, theories that fail to engage the proliferating
and intensifying problems of capitalist globalization, that do not articulate
the continuities between the old and the new, and that renounce the normative
resources of criticism are severely limiting. Failure to provide justification
(of a nonmetaphysical kind), or defense of critical theories and alternative
visions of what history, social life, and our relation to the natural world
could be, continue to be necessary to the project of understanding and changing
the world. We are in a troubling and exciting twilight period, in the
crossroads between modernity and postmodernity, and the task ahead is to forge
reconstructed maps and politics adequate to the great challenges we face.
References
Antonio, Robert J. (1995)
"Nietzsche and Classical Social Theory." American Journal of
Sociology 101(1): 1-43.
Best,
Steven (1995) The Politics of Historical Vision: Marx, Foucault, and
Habermas. New York: Guilford Press.
Best,
Steven and Douglas Kellner (1990) "Kierkegaard, Mass Media, and The
Corsair Affair," International Kierkegaard Commentary, edited
by Robert Perkins, 1990, 23-62.
Best,
Steven and Douglas Kellner (1991) Postmodern Theory: Critical Interrogations,
co-authored with Steven Best. London and New York: Macmillan and Guilford
Press, 1991; Chinese translation 1995.
Best,
Steven and Douglas Kellner (1997) The Postmodern Turn. New York and London:
Guilford Press and Routledge.
Best,
Steven and Douglas Kellner (2001) The Postmodern Adventure. New York and
London: Guilford Press and Routledge.
Boggs, Carl (2000) The End of Politics. New York:
Guilford Press.
Derrida, Jacques (1973) Speech and Phenomena, and Other Essays on
Husserl’s Theory of Signs, Evanston: Northwestern
University Press.
Derrida, Jacques (1976) Of Grammatology, Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press.
Derrida, Jacques (1981a) Positions, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Derrida, Jacques (1981b) Margins of Philosophy, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Dostoevsky,
Fyodor (1974) Notes From Underground. New York: Bantam Books.
Foucault,
Michel (1979) Discipline and Punish, New York: Vintage.
Foucault,
Michel (1982) "The Subject and Power," in Michel Foucault: Beyond
Structuralism and Hermeneutics, ed. by Hubert L. Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow,
pp. 208-226.
Foucault,
Michel (1989) Foucault Live. New York: Semiotext(e).
Foucault,
Michel (1991) Remarks on Marx. New York: Semiotext(e).
Habermas, Jürgen (1987a) Lectures on The Philosophical Discourse of
Modernity, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Hassan, Ihab (1987) The Postmodern Turn: Essays in Postmodern Theory
and Culture, Columbus.
Heidegger, Martin (1977) The Question Concerning Technology, New York: Harper & Row.
Jameson, Fredric (1981) The Political Unconscious, New York: Cornell University Press.
Jameson, Fredric (1984) ‘Postmodernism, or the Cultural Logic of Late
Capitalism’, in New Left Review, no.
146, pp. 53-93.
Kearney, Richard (1988) The Wake of Imagination, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Kellner,
Douglas (1973) Heidegger’s Concept of Authenticity. Ph. Dissertation,
Columbia University.
Kellner,
Douglas (1989) Jean Baudrillard: From Marxism to Post-Modernism and Beyond.
Cambridge, England and Palo Alto, Cal.: Polity Press and Stanford University
Press.
Kellner,
Douglas (1991) "Nietzsche and Modernity: Reflections on Twilight of the
Idols," International Studies in Philosophy, XXIII/2: 3-17.
Kellner,
Douglas (1997) "Intellectuals, the Public Sphere, and New
Technologies," in Research in Philosophy and Technology, Vol. 16:
15-32.
Kellner,
Douglas (2001) Grand
Theft 2000 Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield.
Kierkegaard, Soren (1978) Two
Ages: The Age of Revolution and the Present Age. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Kolb, David (1990) Postmodern Sophistications. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Lyotard, Jean-François (1984) The Postmodern Condition, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Lyotard, Jean-François (1988c) The Differend, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Lyotard, Jean-François and Thebaud, Jean-Loup (1985) Just Gaming, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
McCarthy,
Thomas (1991) Ideals and Illusions: On Reconstruction and Deconstruction in
Contemporary Critical Theory. Cambridge: MIT.
McGowan, John (1991) Postmodernism
and Its Critics. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.
O' Farrell, Clare (1989). Foucault:
Historian or Philosopher. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Ricoeur, Paul (1984) Time and Narrative,
vol. 1, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Rorty, Richard (1989) Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rorty,
Richard (1998) Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century
America. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Vattimo, Gianni (1988) The
End of Modernity. London: Polity Press.
Notes
[1] For our own perspectives on the modern and the postmodern, see Kellner and Best 1991, 1997, and 2001.
[2]. In his book The Present Age, a commentary on a popular novel
with that title, Kierkegaard (1978) distinguishes between antiquity and modern
society and the previous Age of Revolution and the present age (i.e. the 1840s)
as characterized by a precipitous decline in passion; see our detailed analysis
of this text in Best and Kellner 1990 and 1997.
[3]. On Nietzsche's critique of modernity see Kellner 1991; on the neglect
of Nietzsche in classical social theory, see Antonio 1994; and on Nietzsche and
the postmodern, see Best and Kellner 1997.
[4] For further discussions of our positions on Foucault, Lyotard, and postmodern theory, see Best and Kellner 1991 and 1997.
[5] In fact, there is evidence
that Foucault holds a similar position, that his intention is not to renounce
normative discourse in general, but only the normative pronouncements of intellectuals,
or, more restrictively, of Foucault himself, in order to allow for individual
and public choice and debate. Thus, while Foucault refuses to say whether or or
not democracy is "better than" totalitarianism, he does not prohibit
this distinction from being made by others: "I do not wish, as an
intellectual, to play the moralist or prophet. I don't want to say that the
Western countries are better than the ones of the Eastern bloc, etc. The masses
have come of age, politically and morally. They are the ones who've got to
choose individually and collectively" (1991: 172). For further discussion
of the normative problems in critical theory, and an extended comparison of
Foucault and Habermas, see Best (1995).